#especially theological aesthetics and hes such a subject
Explore tagged Tumblr posts
Note
naamah i cant lie i am sooo curious and wanna hear more about you and argenti, if you have anyyy crumbs please :’) ♥️
HII Gray my love 🖤🖤🖤 your question made me run in circles for a bit fkfkgk. Honestly i want to hate him so much and hit him with a cartoonishly huge mallet!! He's so upsetting and silly and i just need to hold him like a little hámster Gray, help???
Okay so this is my evil selfship and villain origin story and wish i could hate Argenti but he's so baby and so dear to me bye. Actually just found him silly and ridiculous and wanted to slap the shit out of him at first but suppose I had the odd thought of "hmm its no good bc bet he'd like that :/ besides it would be kinda hot" and then it was downhill so fast for me 😭
The thing is i can't be mean to my men because then i feel sad and immediately want to make up for that by being nice and ig that was our whole dynamic until I warmed up (unwillingly) to him?
Other than that i think we share the same brand of over the top ridiculousness and to think he's just a little guy who finds beauty in even a houseplant and goes just wandering around the universe helping others is just so T-T sobbing.
He's my knight, my prince, my boytoy, my preraphaelite muse, my thesis topic, my amoeba under microscope, my artsy lewd photography subject. and my little lapdog too if that makes sense, i would literally guard him from evil... I'm his Lamia, his belle dame sans merci, his scary witch wife figuratively. i get in front of him and tell the cashier he asked for no pickles,, i have him by a collar of thorns, i unfortunately just feed into his silliness and delusions all the time.
Want to say so badly i am the only person who gets on his nerves enough to actually upset him (besides boothill probably?) and make him get into honest to god arguments dropping the good faith thing and losing his """cool""" but unfortunately that also works like two times before he figures out i just get a rise of seeing him angry and flustered and being mean on purpose and he's like. Oh. And i lose every bit of that upper hand quickly >_<. Probably the only instance he gets ahead and teases me for a change...
#Surely theres a deeper reasoning to this selfship because i swear im a nerd for the concept of (philosophical) aesthetics#especially theological aesthetics and hes such a subject#i wanna put him under a microscope and study him for ages in all seriousness#his character is unfathomably deep and interesting to me ughhh but lets keep moving.. im normal#thank you so much for your interst gray😘😘😘 even if it comes from the place of a concerned friend going “why him...”#or the friend subject to one's cringe boyfriend as collateral damage <3 luv you#asks
4 notes
·
View notes
Note
You're a druid and an ex-evangelical, right? What does being a druid mean to you? How did you get from evangelicalism to where you are now? And of course feel free to ignore this if it's nosy. (sincerely, a Christian who wants to leave but who doesn't know what to do)
this is going to make me sound ignorant as hell, lol, but i'm happy to share
under a cut because this got very long, sorry, lol.
my personal progression was: "vaguely christian -> VERY christian -> christian agnostic -> agnostic/atheist -> agnostic/druid -> some sorta druid-neopagan-animist thing." i guess i'll just go through what made me switch between each of those, and close out with some high-level thoughts that may be helpful for you?
okay, so when i was
VAGUELY CHRISTIAN,
i went to Sunday school every week because That's What You Do, and because my whole hometown was very southern Baptist, i never questioned the veracity of its teachings much... until they ran a whole weekly series on "why [x] is wrong," where [x] is some other group
e.g., we had a week on why Mormons are wrong, and i didn't bat an eye because i hadn't even known Mormons existed until that moment
then we had a week on why Muslims are wrong, and that... bothered me, because i had a friend who was Muslim, and she was just objectively a better person than me, and i was like "any universe where she goes to hell and i don't seems really fucked up"
then we had a week on why EVOLUTION was wrong, and that just absolutely threw me, because while i hadn't thought about evolution much (i think i was in fourth grade or so), it seemed common-sense? scientists thought highly of it? "adaptation over time" just seems logical?
so i went to the public library every day after school for like a week, read some Darwin and some science books, and came back to my Sunday school teacher with, like, an itemized list of objections to the whole "evolution is wrong" thing. and he came up with some standard Answers In Genesis rebuttals, and i did more research and came back the next week with more science, and we repeated this a few times until he was like "lua, you just gotta take some things on faith"
which. lmao. full existential crisis time, because no matter how hard i thought, i couldn't *not* believe in the science, but i also didn't want to go to hell, so i was like "maybe if i believe SUPER HARD i will SOMEDAY be able to unbelieve the condemn-me-to-hell bits"
so i decided to become
VERY CHRISTIAN
and my frantic googling for shit like "proof of god" and "god and evolution" *eventually* broke me out of the Answers In Genesis circles of the internet, and into some decent Christian apologia, like, think First Things and various Catholic bloggers. and there, i found some way to square my gut sense that evolution was right, with a spiritual worldview.
like, i remember finding some blogger who said:
"young earth creationists get tripped up when they try to explain stars that are millions of light-years away, and end up basically arguing that God's tricking us somehow, and—no! my God lets you believe in the evidence of your eyes, my God does not demand that you make yourself ignorant or stupid, my God expects you to use your brain"
and i just started crying at my computer, because no one had ever said "using your brain is Good and part of God's will," i was like *finally* here's someone who won't tell me i'm going to hell for just *thinking* about things
(st. augustine does a much better riff on a similar theme, fwiw, but i only found him later)
still, it was an uneasy fit, because, the more i learned and read about world history, the more it seemed... weird... that the One And Singular Path To Salvation was... the successor to some niche desert cult... which didn't even occur at the *beginning* of written history, like, it was all predated by that whole Mithraism thing, etc... and like, sure, i could trot out all the standard theological talking points for why Actually This Makes Perfect Sense, but gut-level-wise, the aesthetics just seemed kinda dumb! and no level of talking myself out of it made that feeling go away!
so at this point i started referring to myself as a
CHRISTIAN AGNOSTIC
i mean, not aloud. i still lived in southernbaptistopia and i didn't want, like, my hair stylist to tell me i was a horrible person. but in my *head* i called myself Christian agnostic and it felt right.
and i started church-hopping, which honestly was really fun, would recommend to anyone at any point. i visited the fire-and-brimstone baptist church, the methodist church, the episcopalians, the universal unitarians, etc.
unfortunately, while this gave me *some* new perspectives, each of the places either had the same shitty theology as my old megachurch (i remember the *acute* sense of despair i felt when i was starting to jive with a methodist church... only for the dumbass youth minister to start going on about evolution), or, they just lacked any sense of the *sacred*. like, the Church of Christ churches, with their a capella services, *definitely* had it; i felt more God there in one service than i did in a lifetime of shitty Christian rock at the megachurch. but their beliefs were even *more* batshit, so. big L on that one.
having failed to find a satisfactory church, i was basically
AGNOSTIC/ATHEIST
by the time i went to college, but honestly pretty unhappy about it; while it was harder than ever for me to actually *connect* with the divine, i didn't like thinking that my previous experiences of the divine were total lies. because my shitty evangelical church, for all its faults, could not *completely* sabotage the sense of God's presence. there were real moments in that church where i do believe i experienced something divine. mostly mediated by one particular youth minister, who in hindsight was the only spiritual teacher in that church who didn't seem a bit rotten inside, but! it was something!
so when i happened upon a bunch of writings on the now-defunct shii.org (that's the bit that makes me look WILDLY ignorant, lol), i was utterly captivated.
said author was a previous archdruid of the Reformed Druids of North America, an organization that was formed in the 1960s to troll the administration of Carleton College (there was a religious-service-attendance requirement; they made their own religion; their religion had whiskey and #chilltimes for its services). however, this shii.org dude seemed to take it pretty seriously. he was studying history of religion and blogged a lot about his studies, both academic and otherwise. while RDNA had started out as a troll, that didn't mean they hadn't *discovered* something real in the process, he said.
this, already, was going to be innately appealing to me; i've got a soft spot for wow-we-were-doing-this-ironically-but-now-it's-kinda-real? stuff in general.
in particular, shii.org’s discussions on the separation of ritual from belief was really interesting to me: most religions/spiritualities have *both*, but like, you can do a ritual without having the Exact Right Beliefs (if there even is such a thing!), and it can still be useful to you, it can have real power. (he had a really lovely essay, speculating on the origins of religion as just a form of art, but that essay is now lost to the sands of time, alas.)
(note that i wouldn't really recommend seeking out *recent* writing by the shii.org guy; he kinda went full tedious neoreactionary-blowhard-who-reads-a-lot-of-Spengler at some point? sigh.)
the shii.org guy led me to checking out a bunch of books on the history of neopaganism & also books by scholars of religion in general, and the more i read, the more excited i became. and i started doing little ritual/meditation stuff here and there.
then i was fortunate enough to attend some events with Earthspirit (this was when i lived in Boston), which cemented my hippie dalliances into something more real. the folks there, being from Boston, were all ridiculously overeducated (a sensibility that appeals to me), but also, being the kind of folks who drive out to a mountain in the middle of nowhere for a spiritual retreat, they tolerated a full range of oddities (everyone from aging-70s-feminist-wiccans to living-on-a-farm-with-your-bros-Astaru to dude-who-started-having-weird-visions-and-is-just-trying-to-figure-out-the-deal to Nordic-spiritualist-with-two-phds-from-Scandanavian-universities-on-the-subject, etc), which gave me a lot of room to explore different types of rituals, ceremonies, "magic", etc.
(polytheism in general lends itself well to this sort of easy plurality! i can believe other people are experiencing something real with their gods, and i can be talking to a totally different set of gods, and that’s just all very compatible, etc)
anyway, i started calling myself
AGNOSTIC/DRUID
around then, because i knew i'd found *something*, something that felt like all the realest moments i'd ever had in nature, and all the realest moments i'd ever had in that shitty megachurch, but i wasn't quite ready to put a theology to it.
but, idk, you do the thing for a while, and you start encountering some things that you may as well call gods, and you realize you're in pretty deep, and you ditch the "agnostic" bit and just throw hands and start describing yourself as
SOME SORTA DRUID-NEOPAGAN-ANIMIST THING
because that's the most precise thing you can muster. in particular, the druid bit resonates because nature's still very much at the center of my practice; the neopagan bit resonates because i'm not especially interested in reconstructing older traditions or being faithful to any actual pre-Christian traditions, and animist resonates because what i sometimes call gods seem to be tied pretty tightly to the land itself. it's all very experiential; all this mostly means i'm some weird chick who sometimes grabs a car and drives out someplace very lonely and hikes for a while and does some hippie shit to try and talk with the land or the god or whatever is there. and sometimes i come back from it changed, or refocused, or what-have-you, and hopefully i'm better for it. i'm aware this makes me look a little ridiculous, and is an unsatisfying answer, sorry!
WRT YOUR SITUATION
i don't know you or your situation, obviously, but if i wanted to give former-me some advice to save her some angst, i'd say
-> Christendom itself is far wilder and more diverse than many churches lead you to believe. if you still want to be Christian on some level, and it's just a shitty church that's convinced you the whole project is fucked, i'd honestly explore, i dunno, your nearest Quaker meeting. they're invoking the Holy Spirit with regularity but they're not raging douchenozzles about it.
-> if you're specifically interested in druidism, i found John Michael Greer's "A World Full of Gods" really nice. (caveat: Greer has *also* gone full right-wing nutjob these days, sigh, so like. would not recommend a great swath of his writing. but that one's good)
-> deciding that a just God wouldn't give me a brain and then ask me not to use it was hugely comforting to me. like, that was the start of the whole process, that was what made me feel ok searching for other churches and trying to find something that fit. obviously you should take this with 800 grains of salt, because obviously i'm no longer Christian, and thus maybe i'm just some poor misguided fallen soul, but... i still kinda believe that! maybe if you can make yourself believe that, it'll seem less scary?
idk, happy to answer more questions, sorry for the long ramble, hope it helped~
23 notes
·
View notes
Text
“ Should the Haruspex attempt to autopsy her body on Day 11, he will make the curious discovery that Aglaya does not appear to have any organs. However, looting her body reveals she is carrying a Revolver. “
trawling some highly enjoyable patho wiki content. Congratulations Aglaya Lilich on becoming a Body without Organs, with a gun! you go girl!
“Aglaya contends with God. Those she touches begin to rebel against the established order of things. At the same time, Aglaya is the voice of the law. She sees the universe as a machine. She maintains that the logic of the universe is above everything—polyhedrons be damned. To her, contending with God, too, is a form of restoring justice and natural law. Those she touches begin to realize that there are limits of what’s possible, and they must be accepted with humility.”
Humility
“I should have written nothing[1] at all, but it is far too late for that. Sin and guilt[2] have entered the world[3]— never mind where from, since in any case it would do no good to close that box — and I am no longer striding the crests of my dreams, filling my lungs with air and expelling it again, now instead I am manipulating the keys of a machine[4] striving to thus let my dreams pour and play out across the space of an information-obsessed plane of existence.
There exists no good reason[5] to occupy this space, especially when I have the heights and depths of life wholly available to me at any moment, and yet something compels me, God help me.[6] I have no hope that I will save anyone this way. Not even myself. I know I will not even reach to prevent the wretched[7] from abusing whatever I create. It is a fact that to take something from oneself and put it out into the world is to let it escape and become everything you didn’t want it to be. They say this is so for God the Father as for every human father. I do not believe in either one, but their stories both hold a strange beauty for me.
One can create a monster[8] or a babe; the difference is purely aesthetic. But it is this question of creation. Many simply put it aside, to their own loss. They still create things but they deny they are doing so. They are befallen by atrophy.[9] Others take on the question of creation by accepting the market assurance that whatever makes money must be good because, so the logic goes, people buy things that are good.[10] They become lost to the world of production. Others, in reaction to this, turn toward smaller and smaller circles to keep their creatures safe from the real world. But these spaces are either infected by the social disease or else suffocate for lack of oxygen.
There are some rare exceptions. No one can say where they come from. They destroy all that has come before. They blow into a dying ember. Without them there would be nothing at all.
Now, we have to say that the whole world without them would be an empty[11] dull[12] pale[13] and suffocating lifeless and deathless nothingness, and that they themselves are also a nothingness, but an ecstatic explosion of creative destructive nothingness. So it will be worth keeping in mind that there is a huge and unspeakable gap between the qualities of different sorts of nothingness. Otherwise everything will be overcome by an immense confusion.[14]
The first aspect which ensures that there is something interesting rather than nothing is the explosive energy of the sun. The second is the implosive energy of the earth. These provide for the habitation of a thin membrane where their intercourse takes place. Here there exists a tension between them. Much life forms by rebelling against being crushed into the bowels of the earth and the depths of the sea, whether this rebellion is volcanic, evaporative, or organic. Life must protect itself from being lost in the emptiness of space or scorched in the heat of the sun, and so it also flows, crumbles, burrows, glides, swims, falls and floats downward. This might be all, were it not for something else. Organization, organism, orgasm.[15]”
-Musings on Nothingness (And Some of It’s Varieties)
“Producing, a product: a producing/product identity. It is this identity that constitutes a third term in the linear series: an enormous undifferentiated object. Everything stops dead for a moment, everything freezes in place—and then the whole process will begin all over again. From a certain point of view it would be much better if nothing worked, if nothing functioned. Never being born, escaping the wheel of continual birth and rebirth, no mouth to suck with, no anus to shit through. Will the machines run so badly, their component pieces fall apart to such a point that they will return to nothingness and thus allow us to return to nothingness?
It would seem, however, that the flows of energy are still too closely connected, the partial objects still too organic, for this to happen. What would be required is a pure fluid in a free state, flowing without interruption, streaming over the surface of a full body. Desiring-machines make us an organism; but at the very heart of this production, within the very production of this production, the body suffers from being organized in this way, from not having some other sort of organization, or no organization at all. "An incomprehensible, absolutely rigid stasis" in the very midst of process, as a third stage: "No mouth. No tongue. No teeth. No larynx. No esophagus. No belly. No anus."
The automata stop dead and set free the unorganized mass they once served to articulate. The full body without organs is the unproductive, the sterile, the unengendered, the unconsumable. Antonin Artaud discovered this one day, finding himself with no shape or form whatsoever, right there where he was at that moment. The death instinct: that is its name, and death is not without a model. For desire desires death also, because the full body of death is its motor, just as it desires life, because the organs of life are the working machine. We shall not inquire how all this fits together so that the machine will run: the question itself is the result of a process of abstraction.”
-Anti-Oedipus ch. 1, “THE DESIRING MACHINES”
youtube
I can't stitch it together… but I can cut the knot.
We're all just… dancing on our strings.
Whenever I trace the edges of possibility on a map, I find myself reaching for an eraser not soon after…
Imagine a sphere. See it in your mind's eye. Now lay it out flat. Why is that so easy, when topology is so hard?
We live under the shadow of a higher power… I just despise it.
Only a fool would cut the Gordian knot. It ought to be… vivissected.
The squeal of the gears can't halt the machine.
Why do they insist on torturing me?
There is an immutable and rational order that fate itself has composed. All things run their inevitable courses, down the topology of the universe, toward the mass of this black gravity.
Let's open it. Carefully. And tally the contents.
The judgment of God, the system of the judgment of God, the theological system, is precisely the operation of He who makes an organism, an organization of organs called the organism, because He cannot bear the BwO, because He pursues it and rips it apart so He can be first, and have the organism be first. The organism is already that, the judgment of God, from which medical doctors benefit and on which they base their power. The organism is not at all the body, the BwO; rather, it is a stratum on the BwO, in other words, a phenomenon of accumulation, coagulation, and sedimentation that, in order to extract useful labor from the BwO, imposes upon it forms, functions, bonds, dominant and hierarchized organizations, organized transcendences.
The strata are bonds, pincers. “Tie me up if you wish.“ We are continually stratified. But who is this we that is not me, for the subject no less than the organism belongs to and depends on a stratum? Now we have the answer: the BwO is that glacial reality where the alluvions, sedimentations, coagulations, foldings, and recoilings that compose an organism—and also a signification aid a subject—occur. For the judgment of God weighs upon and is exercised against the BwO; it is the BwO that undergoes it. It is in the BwO that the organs enter into the relations of composition called the organism.
The BwO howls: “They’ve made me an organism! They’ve wrongfully folded me! They’ve stolen my body!��� The judgment of God uproots it from its immanence and makes it an organism, a signification, a subject. It is the BwO that is stratified. It swings between two poles, the surfaces of stratification into which it is recoiled, on which it submits to the judgment, and the plane of consistency in which it unfurls and opens to experimentation.
If the BwO is a limit, if one is forever attaining it, it is because behind each stratum, encasted in it, there is always another stratum. For many a stratum, and not only an organism, is necessary to make the judgment of God. A perpetual and violent combat between the plane of consistency, which frees the BwO, cutting across and dismantling all of the strata, and the surfaces of stratification that block it or make it recoil.
- “ Deleuze/Guattari; How Do You Make Yourself a Body Without Organs? “
youtube
(every morning i listen to confessional, i don’t give a shit bout the bulk ov it, still i keep it professional. and as penance i tell em to proselytize, say the sun is red, say that i am red, say that all their bases belong to us)
The crack Where is the crack? When did I crack?
Then I’ll stand alone on a planet with Nothing left to remember it And I’ll try, I’ll try, I’ll try to prevent it I’ll try, I’ll try, but I’ll never stop it, no
Muzzle me, muzzle muzzle me Bind my will and break of me And you try, you try, you try to prevent it You’ll try, you’ll try, but you’ll never stop it, no
because, laugh if you like, what has been called microbes is god, and do you know what the Americans and the Russians use to make their atoms? They make them with the microbes of god.
- I am not raving. I am not mad. I tell you that they have reinvented microbes in order to impose a new idea of god.
They have found a new way to bring out god and to capture him in his microbic noxiousness.
This is to nail him though the heart, in the place where men love him best, under the guise of unhealthy sexuality, in that sinister appearance of morbid cruelty that he adopts whenever he is pleased to tetanize and madden humanity as he is doing now.
He utilizes the spirit of purity and of a consciousness that has remained candid like mine to asphyxiate it with all the false appearances that he spreads universally through space and this is why Artaud le Mômo can be taken for a person suffering from hallucinations.
- What do you mean, Mr. Artaud?
- I mean that I have found the way to put an end to this ape once and for all and that although nobody believes in god any more everybody believes more and more in man.
So it is man whom we must now make up our minds to emasculate.
- How's that?
No matter how one takes you you are mad, ready for the straitjacket.
- By placing him again, for the last time, on the autopsy table to remake his anatomy. I say, to remake his anatomy. Man is sick because he is badly constructed. We must make up our minds to strip him bare in order to scrape off that animalcule that itches him mortally,
For you can tie me up if you wish, but there is nothing more useless than an organ.
To Have Done With the Judgement of God
10 notes
·
View notes
Text
Terra Ignota
Over the last few weeks, I read Terra Ignota. I read all of the three published books so far: Too Like the Lightning, Seven Surrenders, and The Will to Battle.
Every review of Terra Ignota I have ever read is wrong. Or rather, every review of Terra Ignota I have ever read takes an extremely different perspective to my own, to the extent that I genuinely don’t understand how the author could have concluded that.
So as not to keep anyone in suspense, my perspective on Terra Ignota is that they are surprisingly trashy books, in a world that doesn’t make very much sense, but that doesn’t matter because the heart and soul of these texts is over-the-top soap opera drama. I think they are probably bad, and they outright offended me at several points, but nonetheless they drew me in enough that I wanted to keep reading. There is merit in that.
If you’re the sort of person who cares about spoilers, this is your only warning.
As I said, I don’t understand most of the reviews I have read of these books. I simply don’t.
I don’t understand the view that the writing itself is poetic and beautiful. Palmer has some good phrases from time to time, but overall I don’t find the prose particularly amazing. This is a very subjective point, so I won’t belabour it.
I don’t understand the view that the books are a masterful triumph of worldbuilding. From my perspective, the worldbuilding is actually kind of half-assed, and more importantly, Palmer does not seem to actually care about worldbuilding that much. It isn’t her priority. Reading the books I found myself constantly asking “How does X actually work?” or “Y sounds totally insane, could you explain how it makes sense to me?” or “Z seems like it clashes with X, please resolve this contradiction for me?”, and Palmer never answers those questions for you. If I want some more explanation for why, say, a global transportation system serving billions of people is run without oversight, from a single private residence, looked after by a man well-known to be suicidally depressed… nope, I’m not getting that. If I want some context for how hive-switching works, or how it interacts with crime, not happening. Even minor questions: in The Will to Battle, our heroes talk to a band of criminals involved in human trafficking, and I immediately wanted to know what human trafficking means in a world where borders have been abolished, geographic nations have been abolished, and every place on Earth is just a short taxi ride from every other place. This is the sort of question Palmer does not answer or even acknowledge.
And I don’t actually buy that she’s interested in the questions that I see raised when the books are spruiked to me. Are you intrigued by the question of what the world would look like if every individual could choose their own government, their own law code, unconstrained by geography? I’m intrigued by that. It sounds interesting. But this is not a question that Terra Ignota is actually interested in. It seems like it should be interested in it, and I read enough breathless expositions of how cool the hive system is that I expected Terra Ignota to be interested in it… but it’s not. If you’re interested in, say, the question of whether a permanent exit option would make absolute dictatorship more humane, as in the Masons, then I agree that’s interesting – but it is not a question that the text of Terra Ignota takes any interest in. The big worldbuilding questions raised by the hives are all window dressing.
I don’t understand the idea that Terra Ignota is a brilliant depiction of utopia. I want to acknowledge straight off the bat that I may have a bias here, because Terra Ignota’s world is premised on the, well, genocide of people like me, or at least the forcible suppression and exile of people like me, but I don’t think it’s only the fact that I’m openly in defiance of the First Black Law. Rather, I note two things here. Firstly, it’s hard to see whether Terra Ignota’s society is actually utopian because we spend so little time in it. We do not see how ordinary people live in this world, or what makes it wonderful. What Terra Ignota spends most of its time on is the scheming and backstabbing of the dozen most powerful people in the world, and everyone outside that little circle barely exists in the text. (Abigail Nussbaum noted in her review that Terra Ignota’s world never really feels like it has more than a few hundred people in it, and I agree.) It’s hard to convincingly argue Terra Ignota is a utopia or a dystopia, because we never meet the whole population. We meet a small handful of amoral nobility as they play out a space opera Game of Thrones. That’s certainly entertaining, and I give Palmer credit for making it fun to read, but it’s not really an investigation of utopia. Secondly, where we do see glimpses of the world outside the parlours of the ruthless rich, it…honestly seems rather conventional, and rather like the 21st century. People work fewer hours a week, taxis are much more efficient, movies have smelltracks as well as soundtracks, they go to the Olympics, apparently the Oscars endured the collapse of all nations and religions… but there is little in this world that seems radically different to our own. It’s all minor, incremental bits of technological progress. They’ve eliminated poverty, which is good, but I usually expect something more radical from utopia than that. What do people actually do in Terra Ignota that’s different to what any upper-middle class American might do today? Other, of course, than not go to church, call everyone singular they, and wear tracking devices.
I don’t understand the idea that these books deal with deep philosophical or theological themes. Like the hives themselves, it’s all window dressing. The narrator Mycroft is obsessed with the 18th century, and so is a bizarre anachronistic brothel that somehow every major world leader attends (cf. worldbuilding being weak, the world only feeling like it has a few hundred people in it), but they don’t do very much with this. Mycroft imagines Thomas Hobbes occasionally butting in, but his imaginary Hobbes has little to say beyond "Hi, I’m the guy who wrote Leviathan!” The characters reference Diderot and de Sade and Voltaire, but usually only on the surface level, and when they do try to go deeper, they often get the references wrong. The same for the theology. My point is not that Terra Ignota is bad: just that it isn’t really that interested in the political philosophy or the theology. It uses 18th century thought as an aesthetic. Deism, miracles, proof of God’s existence, how gods might communicate, etc., are not the questions that occupy the text. Ada Palmer is not a theologian.
But all that said, I enjoyed Terra Ignota.
I want to emphasise that. I enjoyed Terra Ignota! I am not saying that it’s bad! I’m just saying that it was not what everyone told me it would be.
Terra Ignota is a book about a bunch of very powerful, very horrible people, who all apparently go to the same brothel and are interested in the same wacky theories about human nature and God and so on, lying to and betraying each other. I think Palmer is really interested in the characters. Mycroft, our pretentious narrator who by the end of book three is genuinely losing his grip on reality and writing hallucinations. Jedd Mason, the madman who believes he’s God, but is probably just the delusional product of a radical set-set experiment. Caesar, the iron-proud absolute dictator seeking to do his duty by his ambitious, power-obsessed hive. Dominic, the sadistic sexual predator who nonetheless worships Jedd with fanatical devotion. Carlyle, the kind and compassionate philosopher-in-residence who inevitably gets tortured and abused. Ojiro Sniper, the freaky sex doll who nonetheless seeks to become the Brutus to Jedd’s Caesar. Apollo Mojave, the dead-but-still-influential space wizard who sought to cause a world war for stupid reasons. And so on. The characters are generally well-drawn and interesting enough that I want to see what happens to them.
I should emphasise Palmer’s achievement in making me want to know what happens to these people, especially because they’re all so unsympathetic. Carlyle and Bridger stand out as the most truly sympathetic characters in the novels, but by book three, the former has been captured, tortured, and now limps along, dead-eyed and broken-spirited, in the train of one of the resident sadists, and the latter has quite reasonably gone “Screw this” and used his immense psychic powers to delete himself from the book. But most of the core characters in this drama – Mycroft, Saladin, Jedd, Sniper, Ganymede and Danae, Madame d’Arouet, etc. – are mad, evil, both, or otherwise extremely unsympathetic. It is to Palmer’s credit that I want to know what happens in the war anyway. The most sympathetic of the political leaders in the text, Vivien Ancelet and Bryar Kosala, spend most of their time fruitlessly begging for peace. While they, perhaps alone of the leaders, have genuinely laudable intentions, it has been clear from the first book that neither will be permitted to achieve anything notable. The only people to barrack for, in Terra Ignota, are those noble if compromised few who seek to avoid a war – and who we all know will fail.
Book four, it seems, will finally be about the war that the first three books have been setting up, and even though I frankly want all three sides to lose – the Jedd faction, the Sniper faction, and Utopia are all deeply unpleasant, albeit in different ways – I am sure I will find it extremely entertaining to see how this all collapses.
Do I recommend Terra Ignota? I don’t know. If you want detailed, thorough worldbuilding, sincere contemplation of deep philosophical questions about theodicy, politics, and human nature, or a stirring vision of a possible utopia… no. Do not read it for those things. It does not have those things in it.
But it does have a scene where the prime minister of Europe body-tackles the Olympic president through a plate glass window and they land in a pile of people having sex mid-orgy, while the media broadcasts it worldwide.
And that’s excellent.
6 notes
·
View notes
Text
The Darkest Philosopher in History - Arthur Schopenhauer
Being one of the first philosophers to ever
really question the value of existence,
to systematically combine eastern
and western modes of thinking,
and to introduce the arts as a serious
philosophical focus, Arthur Schopenhauer
is perhaps one of the darkest and most
comprehensive philosophers in western history.
Schopenhauer was born in 1788 in what is
now Gdansk, Poland, but spent the majority
of his childhood in Hamburg, Germany after
his family moved there when he was five.
He was born to a wealthy family, his father
being a highly successful international merchant.
As a result of this, young Schopenhauer would
be expected to follow in his father’s footsteps.
However, from an early age, he had no interest
in business, and instead, found himself compelled
towards academics. And after going on a trip
around Europe with his parents to prepare him
for his merchant career, the greater exposure
he would receive to the pervasive suffering
and poverty of the world would cause him to
become all the more interested in pursuing
the path of scholarship and intellectually
examining, down to its very core, how the
world worked and why—or perhaps more accurately,
how and why it appeared to work so negatively.
After eventually going against his family’s
readymade path of international business,
Schopenhauer would attend the University of
Göttingen in 1809, where, in his third semester,
he would become more introduced and
focused on philosophy. The following year,
he would transfer to the University of Berlin
to study under a better philosophy program led
by distinguished philosophy lecturers of the
time.
However, Schopenhauer would soon find
academic philosophy to be unnecessarily obscure,
detached from real concerns of life, and often
tethered to theological agendas; all of which,
he despised. Eventually, he left the academic,
intellectual circuit, and spent the following
decade philosophizing and writing on his own.
By age thirty, Schopenhauer had published
the two works that would go on to define
his entire career, contain his complete,
unified philosophical system from which
he would never deviate, and eventually influence
the entire course of western thinking with.
The first groundwork of his philosophy
was established in his dissertation,
On the Fourfold Root of the Principle
of Sufficient Reason, published in 1813,
and his entire unified philosophical system,
including his metaphysics, epistemology, ethics,
aesthetics, value judgments, and so forth,
was laid out in his subsequent masterwork,
The World as Will and Representation, published
in 1819. Despite these impressive works going on
to hold major stake in western philosophy,
influencing some of the greatest thinkers
and schools of thought thereafter, during
this time, they would go mostly unnoticed.
Over the decades following his early
work, throughout his thirties and forties,
Schopenhauer would spend his time working to be a
lecturer at university, as well as a translator of
French to English prose, while continuing to write
on-and-off along the side. He found very little
success in all of it. His lectures were unpopular,
his translations received very little interest,
and his philosophical work remained mostly
overlooked. Only by around his fifties,
did Schopenhauer finally start to receive
any notable recognition, at all.
And only
after publishing a book of essays and aphorisms
in 1851, would he achieve the status of fame,
which he would remain in for the rest of his life
until he died in 1860 at the age of seventy-two.
In terms of Schopenhauer’s philosophical system
established within his work, it is relevant to
note that it leaned heavily on the work of his
predecessor, Immanuel Kant. In Schopenhauer’s
mind, he was completing Kant’s system of
transcendental idealism. Building off his
interpretation of Kant, Schopenhauer essentially
suggested that the world as we know and experience
it, is exclusively a representation created by our
mind through our senses and forms of cognition.
Consequently, we cannot access the true
nature of external objects outside our mental,
phenomenological experience of them. Deviating
from Kant, however, Schopenhauer would go onto to
argue that not only can we not know nor access the
varying objects of the world as they really are
outside of our conscious experience, but
there is, in fact, no plurality of objects
beyond our experience, at all. Rather, beyond
our experience is, according to Schopenhauer,
a singular, unified oneness of reality—a sort
of essence or force that drives existence
that is beyond time, beyond space, and beyond all
objectivation. Schopenhauer would go on to explore
and define this force by referencing and probing
into the experience of living within the body,
suggesting that this is the only thing
in the world that we have access to
that is not solely a mental representation of
an object but is also a firsthand, subjective
experience from within it. From here, Schopenhauer
would suggest that what is found from within,
at the core of our being, is an unconscious,
restless, striving force towards survival,
nourishment, and reproduction. He would term this
force the Will to live.
Essentially, this would
lead him to the conclusion that reality is made
up of two sides; one side being the plurality
of things as they are represented to a conscious
apparatus, and the other side being the singular,
unified force of the Will—hence the name of his
master work, The World as Will and Representation.
It is worth noting that the term Will can
perhaps be misleading in that it might seem
to imply an intention or human-like conscious
motivation, but the Will, for Schopenhauer,
is a blind, unconscious striving with no goal
or purpose other than to keep itself going
for the sake of keeping itself going. All of the
material world operates by and through this Will,
moving, striving, consuming, and violently
expressing itself in order to sustain itself.
Schopenhauer’s work was largely a response to
Kant and the western philosophical tradition,
but his work also contains distinct notes of
Hinduism and Buddhism. His conclusion of the
nature of reality is strikingly similar to that of
both. And his qualitative assessment of reality’s
negative relationship with the conscious self
mirrors ideas central to Buddhism. This made
Schopenhauer one of the first philosophers to
ever really combine eastern and western thinking
in such a systematically comprehensive way.
Especially similar to Buddhism, Schopenhauer
would top off his philosophical medley with a
layer of dark, unwavering pessimism. “Unless
suffering is the direct and immediate object of
life, our existence must entirely fail of its aim.
It is absurd to look upon the enormous amount
of pain that abounds everywhere in the world,
and originates in needs and necessities
inseparable from life itself, as serving no
purpose at all and the result of mere chance. Each
separate misfortune, as it comes, seems, no doubt,
to be something exceptional; but misfortune in
general is the rule.” Schopenhauer wrote. As a
qualitative assessment of the nature of reality,
he would describe the Will to live as a sort of
malevolent force that we, as individual selves,
become victims of in its process of continuation,
deceived by our own mind and body to go against
our fundamental interests and yearnings in order
to carry it out. Since the Will has no aim or
purpose other than its perpetual continuation,
then the will can never be satisfied. And
since we are expressions of it, neither can we.
Thus, we are driven to consume beings, things,
ideas, goals, circumstances, and all the rest,
constantly hoping we will feel a satisfaction or
happiness as result, while constantly being left
in the wake of each achievement unsatisfied.
"Human life must be some kind of mistake.
The truth of this will be sufficiently obvious if
we only remember that man is a compound of needs
and necessities hard to satisfy; and that even
when they are satisfied, all he obtains is a state
of painlessness, where nothing remains to him
but abandonment to boredom.” Schopenhauer wrote.
As the best possible ways of sort
of escaping and dealing with this,
Schopenhauer would put forth two primary methods:
one, engaging in arts and philosophy, and two, the
practicing of asceticism, traditionally being the
deprivation of nearly all desire, self-indulgence,
and everything past the bare minimum. In this
later method, Schopenhauer felt that by denying
the Will from being fed, so-to-speak, one would
turn the Will against itself and overcome it.
However, he also recognized the sheer
difficulty of this for the majority of people
and suggested the average person should
simply make their best efforts towards
letting go of ideals of happiness and pleasure,
and rather, focus on the minimization of pain.
Happiness in life, for Schopenhauer, is not
a matter of joys and pleasures, but rather,
the reduction and freedom from pain
as much as possible. “The safest way
of not being very miserable is not to
expect to be very happy.” he wrote.
Alternatively, engaging in arts and philosophy,
in Schopenhauer’s mind, served as another, more
accessible method. He felt that good art could
provide a source of clarity into the nature and
problems of being, without any of the illusion or
drapery. And while engaging in this sort of art,
one would have a transcendent-like experience
that provides a relief and comfort from existence.
As a result of this concept,
Schopenhauer would end up being one
of first thinkers to ever really introduce
philosophical significance to the arts,
and would eventually become known by
many as the ‘artist’s philosopher.’
Of course, throughout his work in general,
Schopenhauer makes large, often unprovable,
and unknowable claims about the nature of reality
and the value of existing within it. Some of which
is validly constructed and worth considering,
but some of which is likely not. Ultimately,
any attempt to define and assess the side of
reality beyond logic and reason through systematic
logic and reason is perhaps paradoxical in way
that is beyond repair. What precisely is the Will,
where does it come from, where does it
end, and how can we know or prove it?
And in terms of Schopenhauer’s suggestion
that one should turn against the Will
through an ascetic process of self-denial,
if all of life operates through the Will,
to turn against it, would seem to merely be the
Will turning against the Will for reasons that
favor it. And there can be no turning against
the Will if the Will is doing the turning.
Alternatively, considering the view of Friedrich
Nietzsche, a philosopher who notably followed in
Schopenhauer’s footsteps, the endless cycle of
desire and dissatisfaction caused by the Will
is actually a good thing that we can use as fuel
towards the process of self-overcoming and growth,
which we can then obtain life’s meaning
from. Of course, this is the more pleasant
of the two interpretations, but it isn’t clear
which is more apt and/or accurate, if either.
Ultimately, Schopenhauer is another surprising,
yet seemingly common story where a highly
important thinker, artist, or writer, barely
caught any recognition in their life, if at all,
only to die and end up with their name in
nearly every history book on the subject.
One trait these stories do all
seem to have in common, though,
is a refusal to stop, a refusal to budge from
pursuing and defending the world as one sees it.
Schopenhauer never deviated from the
philosophical system he created in his twenties
and never stopped confidently working to build
upon it and reinforce it throughout his life,
despite the world seeming to suggest to
him he should do otherwise. And yet, now,
it is hugely significant to the world that he did
exactly what he did. For some, his work might be
bleak and disconcerting, but for others, his work,
like all great works of dark, melancholic honesty,
is comforting, relieving, and legitimizing. It
reminds us that are not crazy, and our sadness
and suffering are not unfounded, even when they
may feel like it. We are merely put in a crazy,
sad, violent reality with a mind and body
that are often all in conspiracy against us.
Because of this and many other reasons
unmentioned, his work would go on to
influence artists like Richard Wagner and Gustav
Mahler; writers like Marcel Proust, Leo Tolstoy,
and Samuel Beckett; and thinkers like Friedrich
Nietzsche, Sigmund Freud, and Ludwig Wittgenstein,
as well as many others, ultimately influencing
the course of modern thinking, forever.
Having been one of the first to properly
and philosophically bring the value of life
and the possibility of meaning into question,
Schopenhauer helped locate the early budding
problem of the growing agnostic world
that philosophy would need to address.
With humanity seemingly suspending
further out into a void of meaning,
his unyielding and fearless confrontation with
the nature of existence, including all its
horrors and miseries, revealed an opening of new
possibilities towards finding answers from within.
3 notes
·
View notes
Note
Can you elaborate on Erusamus and the reformation please, or at least point me toward sources? Politics make more sense than philosophy to me, so I see the reformation through the lense of Henry VIII, or the Duke of Prussia who dissolved the teutonic order, or France siding with the protestants during the 30 Years War because Protestants > Hapsburgs
So sorry to take so long!
If you needed this answer for academic reasons, given that summer term is pretty much done I’m probably too late to help, but I hate to leave an ask unanswered.
HELLA LONG ESSAY BENEATH THE CUT SORRY I WROTE SELF-INDULGENTLY WITHOUT EDITING SO THERE IS WAY MORE EXPLANATION THAN YOU PROBABLY NEED
Certainly religion has been politicised, you need look no further than all the medieval kings having squabbles with the pope. Medieval kings were not as devastated by the prospect of excommunication as you’d expect they’d be in a super-devout world, it was kinda more of a nuisance (like, idk, the pope blocking you on tumblr) than the “I’m damned forever! NOOOOOOO!” thing you’d expect. I’m not saying excommunication wasn’t a big deal, but certainly for Elizabeth I she was less bothered than the pope excommunicating her than the fact that he absolved her Catholic subjects of allegiance to her and promised paradise to her assassin (essentially declaring open season on her).
I think, however, in our secular world we forget that religion was important for its own sake. Historians since Gibbon have kind of looked down on religion as its own force, seeing it as more a catalyst for economic change (Weber) or a tool of the powerful. If all history is the history of class struggle, then religion becomes a weapon in class warfare rather than its own force with its own momentum. For example, historians have puzzled over conversion narratives, and why Protestantism became popular among artisans in particular. Protestantism can’t compete with Catholicism in terms of aesthetics or community rituals, it’s a much more interior kind of spirituality, and it involves complex theological ideas like predestination that can sound rather drastic, so why did certain people find it appealing?
(although OTOH transubstantiation is a more complex theological concept than the Protestant idea of “the bread and wine is just bread and wine, it’s a commemoration of the Last Supper not a re-enactment, it aint that deep fam”).
I’ve just finished an old but interesting article by Terrence M. Reynolds in Concordia Theological Quarterly vol. 41 no. 4 pp.18-35 “Was Erasmus responsible for Luther?” Erasmus in his lifetime was accused of being a closet Protestant, or “laying the egg that Luther hatched”. Erasmus replied to this by saying he might have laid the egg, but Luther hatched a different bird entirely. Erasmus did look rather proto Protestant because he was very interested in reforming the Church. He wanted more people to read the Bible, he had a rather idyllic dream of “ploughmen singing psalms as they ploughed their fields”. He criticised indulgences, the commercialisation of relics and pilgrimages and the fact that the Papacy was a political faction getting involved in wars. He was worried that the rituals of Catholicism meant that people were more mechanical in their religion than spiritual: they were memorising the words, doing the actions, paying the Church, blindly believing anything a poorly educated priest regurgitated to them. They were confessing their sins, doing their penances like chores and then going right back to their sins. They were connecting with the visuals, but not understanding and spiritually connecting with the spirit of Jesus’ message and his ideals of peace and love and charity and connecting with God. Erasmus translated the NT but being a Renaissance humanist, he went ad fontes (‘to the source’) and used Greek manuscripts, printing the Greek side by side with the Latin so that readers could compare and see the translation choices he made. His NT had a lot of self-admitted errors in it, but it was very popular with Prots as well as Caths. Caths like Thomas More were cool with him doing it, but it was also admired by Prots like Thomases and Cromwell and Cranmer and Tyndale himself. When coming across Greek words like presbyteros, Erasmus actually chose to leave it as a Greek word with its own meaning than use a Latin word that didn’t *quite* fit the meaning of the original.
However, he did disagree with Protestants on fundamental issues, especially the question of free will. For Luther, the essence was sole fide: salvation through faith alone. He took this from Paul’s letter to the Romans, where it says that through faith alone are we justified. Ie, humans are so fallen (because of the whole Eve, apple, original sin debacle) and so flawed and tainted by sin, and God is so perfect, that we ourselves will never be good enough. All the good works in the world will never reach God’s level of perfection and therefore we all deserve Hell, but we won’t go to hell because God and Jesus will save us from the Hell we so rightly deserve, by grace and by having faith in Jesus’ sacrifice, who will alone redeem us. The opposite end of the free will/sola fide spectrum is something called Pelagianism, named after the guy who believed it, Pelagius, who lived centuries and centuries before the Ref, it’s the belief that humans can earn their salvation by themselves, by good works. Both Caths and Prots considered Pelagius a heretic. Caths like Erasmus believed in a half-way house: God reaches out his hand to save you through Jesus’ example and sacrifice, giving you grace, and you receive his grace, which makes you want to be a good person and do good works (good works being things like confession of sins, penances, the eucharist, charity, fasting, pilgrimages) and then doing the good works means you get more grace and you are finally saved, or at least you will go to purgatory after death AND THEN be saved and go to heaven, rather than going straight to Hell, which is what happens if you reject Jesus and do no good works and never repent your sins. If you don’t receive his grace and do good works, you won’t make the grade for ultimate salvation.
(This is why it’s important to look at the Ref as a theological as well as a political movement because if you only look at the political debates, Erasmus looks more Protestant than he actually was.)
There are several debates happening in the Reformation: the role of the priest (which is easily politicised) free will vs predestination, transubstantiation or no transubstantiation (is or isn’t the bread and wine transformed into the body and blood of Jesus by God acting through the priest serving communion) and the role of scripture. A key doctrine of Protestantism is sola scriptura. Basically: if it’s in the Bible, it’s the rules. If it’s not in the Bible, it’s not in the rules. No pope in the bible? No pope! No rosaries in the bible? No using rosaries! (prayer beads)
However, both Caths and Prots considered scripture v.v. important. Still, given that the Bible contains internal contradictions (being a collection of different books written in different languages at different times by different people) there was a hierarchy of authority when it came to scripture. As a general rule of thumb, both put the New T above the Old T in terms of authority. (This is partly why Jews and Muslims have customs like circumcision and no-eating-pig-derived-meats that Christians don’t have, even though the order of ‘birth’ as it were goes Judaism-Christianity-Islam. All 3 Abrahammic faiths use the OT, but only Christians use the NT.)
1. The words of Jesus. Jesus said you gotta do it, you gotta do it. Jesus said monogamy, you gotta do monogamy. Jesus said no divorce, you gotta do no divorcing (annulment =/= divorce). Jesus said no moneylending with interest (usury), you gotta do no moneylending with interest (which is partly why European Jews did a lot of the banking. Unfortunately, disputes over money+religious hatred is a volatile combination, resulting in accusations of conspiracy and sedition, leading to hate-fuelled violence and oppression.) The trouble with the words of Jesus is that you can debate or retranslate what Jesus meant, especially easily as Jesus often spoke in parables and with metaphors. When Jesus said “this is my body…this is my blood” at the Last Supper, is that or is that not support for transubstantiation? When Jesus called Peter the rock on which he would build the church, was that or was that not support for the apostolic succession that means Popes are the successor to St Peter, with Peter being first Pope? When the gospel writers said Jesus ‘did more things and said more things than are contained in this book’, does that or does that not invalidate the idea of sola scriptura?
2. The other New Testament writers, especially St. Paul and the Relevation of St John the Divine. (Divine meaning like seer, divination, not a god or divinity). These are particularly relevant when it comes to discussing the role of priests and priesthood, only-male ordination, and whether women can preach and teach religion.
3. The Old Testament, especially Genesis.
4. The apocryphal or deuterocanonical works. These books are considered holy, but there’s question marks about their validity, so they’re not as authoritative as the testaments. I include this because the deuterocanonical book 2 Maccabees was used as scriptural justification for the Catholic doctrine of purgatory, but 2 Maccabees is the closest scipture really gets to mentioning any kind of purgatory. Protestants did not consider 2 Maccabees to be strong enough evidence to validate purgatory.
5. The Church Fathers, eg. Origen, Augustine of Hippo. Arguably their authority often comes above apocryphal scripture. It’s from the Church Fathers that the concept of the Trinity (one god in 3 equal persons, God the Father, God the Son, God the Holy Spirit) is developed because it’s not actually spelled out explicitly in the NT. Early modern Catholics and Protestants both adhered to the Trinity and considered Arianism’s interpretation of the NT (no trinity, God the Father is superior to Jesus as God the Son) to be heresy. Church Fathers were important to both Catholics and Protestants: Catholics because Catholics did not see scripture as the sole source of religious truth, so additions made by holy people are okay so long as they don’t *contradict* scripture, and so long as they are stamped with the church council seal of approval, Protestants because they believed that the recent medieval theologians and the papacy had corrupted and altered the original purity of Christianity. If they could show that Church Fathers from late antiquity like Augustine agreed with them, that therefore proved their point about Christianity being corrupted from its holy early days.
Eamon Duffy’s book Stripping of the Altars is useful because it questions the assumptions that the Reformation and Break with Rome was inevitable, or that the Roman Catholic Church was a corrupt relic of the past that had to be swept aside for Progress, or that most people even wanted the Ref in England to happen. Good history essays need to discuss different historians’ opinions and Duffy can be relied upon to have a different opinion than Protestant historians. Diarmaid MacCulloch’s works are good at explaining theological concepts, he is a big authority on church history and he’s won a whole bunch of prizes. He was actually ordained a deacon in the Church of England in the 1980s but stopped being a minister because he was angry with the institution for not tolerating the fact he had a boyfriend. The ODNB is a good source to access through your university if you want to read a quick biography on a particular theologian or philosopher, but it only covers British individuals. Except Erasmus, who has a page on ODNB despite being not British because he’s just that awesome and because his influence on English scholarship and culture was colossal. Peter Marshall also v good, esp on conversion. Euan Cameron wrote a mahoosive book called the European Reformation.“More versus Tyndale: a study of controversial technique” by Rainer Pineas is good for the key differences in translation of essential concepts between catholic and protestant thinkers. The Sixteenth Century Journal is a good source of essays as well.
12 notes
·
View notes
Text
Aristotle's Collection [ 29 Books] - Publish This
Aristotle's Collection [ 29 Books] Publish This Genre: Philosophy Price: $0.99 Publish Date: June 27, 2011 Publisher: Publish This, LLC Seller: Publish This, LLC This contain collection of 29 Books 1. Categories translated by E. M. Edghill 2. On Interpretation translated by E. M. Edghill 3. Prior Analytics translated by A. J. Jenkinson 4. Posterior Analytics translated by G. R. G. Mure 5. Topics translated by W. A. Pickard-Cambridge 6. On Sophistical Refutations translated by W. A. Pickard- Cambridge 7. Physics translated by R. P. Hardie and R. K. Gaye 8. On the Heavens translated by J. L. Stocks 9. On Generation and Corruption translated by H. H. Joachim 10. Meteorology translated by E. W. Webster 11. On the Soul translated by J. A. Smith 12. On sense and the sensible translated by J. I. Beare 13. On memory and reminiscence translated by J. I. Beare 14. On Dreams translated by J. I. Beare 15. On prophesying by dreams translated by J. I. Beare 16. On longevity and shortness of life translated by G. R. T. Ross 17. On Youth, Old Age, Life and Death, and Respiration translated by G. R. T. Ross 18. The History of Animals translated by D'Arcy Wentworth Thompson 19. On the parts of Animals translated by William Ogle 20. On the motion of animals translated by A. S. L. Farquharson 21. On the Gait of Animals translated by A. S. L. Farquharson 22. On the Generation of Animals translated by Arthur Platt 23. Metaphysics translated by W. D. Ross 24. Nicomachean Ethics translated by W. D. Ross 25. Politics translated by Benjamin Jowett 26. The Athenian Constitution translated by Sir Frederic G. Kenyon 27. Rhetoric translated by W. Rhys Roberts 28. Poetics translated by S. H. Butcher 29. On sleep and sleeplessness translated by J. I. Beare About the Author Aristotle (Greek: Ἀριστοτέλης, Aristotélēs) (384 BC – 322 BC) was a Greek philosopher, a student of Plato and teacher of Alexander the Great. He wrote on many subjects, including physics, metaphysics, poetry, theater, music, logic, rhetoric, politics, government, ethics, biology and zoology. Together with Plato and Socrates, Aristotle is one of the most important founding figures in Western philosophy. He was the first to create a comprehensive system of Western philosophy, encompassing morality and aesthetics, logic and science, politics and metaphysics. Aristotle's views on the physical sciences profoundly shaped medieval scholarship, and their influence extended well into the Renaissance, although they were ultimately replaced by Newtonian Physics. In the biological sciences, some of his observations were confirmed to be accurate only in the nineteenth century. His works contain the earliest known formal study of logic, which was incorporated in the late nineteenth century into modern formal logic. In metaphysics, Aristotelianism had a profound influence on philosophical and theological thinking in the Islamic and Jewish traditions in the Middle Ages, and it continues to influence Christian theology, especially Eastern Orthodox theology, and the scholastic tradition of the Catholic Church. All aspects of Aristotle's philosophy continue to be the object of active academic study today. Though Aristotle wrote many elegant treatises and dialogues (Cicero described his literary style as "a river of gold"), it is thought that the majority of his writings are now lost and only about one-third of the original works have survived. http://dlvr.it/R5x5YH
0 notes
Text
Acid Communism, by Mark Fisher (k-punk)
“The spectre of a world which could be free”
“[T]he closer the real possibility of liberating the individual from the constraints once justified by scarcity and immaturity, the greater the need for maintaining and streamlining these constraints lest the established order of domination dissolve. Civilisation has to protect itself against the spectre of a world which could be free.
[…] In exchange for the commodities that enrich their lives […] individuals sell not only their labour but also their free time. […] People dwell in apartment concentrations — and have private automobiles with which they can no longer escape into a different world. They have huge refrigerators stuffed with frozen foods. They have dozens of newspapersand magazines which espouse the same ideals. They have innumerable choices, innumerable gadgets which are all of the same sort and keep them occupied and divert their attention from the real issue — which is the awareness that they could both work less and determine their own needs and satisfactions.” — Herbert Marcuse, Eros and Civlisation
The claim of the book is that the last forty years have been about the exorcising of “the spectre of a world which could be free”. Adopting the perspective of such a world allows us to reverse the emphasis of much recent left-wing struggle. Instead of seeking to overcome capital, we should focus on what capital must always obstruct: the collective capacity to produce, care and enjoy. We on the left have had it wrong for a while: it is not that we are anti-capitalist, it is that capitalism, with all its visored cops, its teargas, and all the theological niceties of its economics, is set up to block the emergence of this Red Plenty. The overcoming of capital has to be fundamentally based on the simple insight that, far from being about “wealth creation”, capital necessarily and always blocks the production of common wealth.
The principal, though by no means the sole, agent involved in the exorcism of the spectre of a world which could be free is the project that has been called neoliberalism. But neoliberalism’s real target was not its official enemies — the decadent monolith of the Soviet bloc, and the crumbling compacts of social democracy and the New Deal, which were collapsing under the weight of their own contradictions. Instead, neoliberalism is best understood as a project aimed at destroying — to the point of making them unthinkable — the experiments in democratic socialism and libertarian communism that were efflorescing at the end of the Sixties and the beginning of the Seventies.
The ultimate consequence of the elimination these possibilities was the condition I have called capitalist realism — the fatalistic acquiescence in the view that there is no alternative to capitalism. If there was a founding event of capitalist realism, it would be the violent destruction of the Allende government in Chile by General Pinochet’s American-backed coup. Allende was experimenting with a form of democratic socialism which offered a real alternative both to capitalism and to Stalinism. The military destruction of the Allende regime, and the subsequent mass imprisonments and torture, are only the most violent and dramatic example of the lengths capital had to go to in order to make itself appear to be the only “realistic” mode of organising society. It wasn’t only that a new form of socialism was terminated in Chile; the country also became a lab in which the measures which would be rolled out in other hubs of neoliberalism (financial deregulation, the opening up of the economy to foreign capital, privatisation) were trialled. In countries like the US and the UK, the implementation of capitalist realism was a much more piecemeal affair, involving inducements and seductions as well as repression. The ultimate effect was the same — the extirpation of the very idea of democratic socialism or libertarian communism.
The exorcising of the “spectre of a world which could be free” was a cultural as well as a narrowly political question. For this spectre, and the possibility of a world beyond toil, was raised most potently in culture — even, or perhaps especially, in culture which didn’t necessarily think of itself as politically-orientated.
Marcuse explains why this is the case, and the declining influence of his work in recent years tells its own story. One-Dimensional Man, a book which emphasises the gloomier side of his work, has remained a reference point, but Eros and Civilisation, like many of his other works, has long been out of print. His critique of capitalism’s total administration of life and subjectivity continued to resonate; whereas the claims Marcuse’s conviction that art constituted a “Great Refusal, the protest against that which is”3 came to seem like outmoded Romanticism, quaintly irrelevant in the age of capitalist realism. Yet Marcuse had already forestalled such criticisms, and the critique in One-Dimensional Man has traction because it comes from a second space, an “aesthetic dimension” radically incompatible with everyday life under capitalism. Marcuse argued that, in actuality, the “traditional images of artistic alienation” associated with Romanticism do not belong to the past. Instead, he said, in… formulation, they “recall and preserve in memory belongs to the future: images of a gratification that would destroy the society that suppresses it.”4
The Great Refusal rejected, not only capitalist realism, but “realism” as such. There is, he wrote, an “inherent conflict between art and political realism”.5 Art was a positive alienation, a “rational negation” of the existing order of things. His Frankfurt School predecessor, Theodor Adorno, had placed a similar value on the intrinsic alterity of experimental art. In Adorno’s work, however, we are invited to endlessly examine the wounds of a damaged life under capital; the idea of a world beyond capital is despatched into a utopian beyond. Art only marks our distance from this utopia. By contrast, Marcuse vividly evokes, as an immediate prospect, a world totally transformed. It was no doubt this quality of his work that meant Marcuse was taken up so enthusiastically by elements of the Sixties counterculture. He had anticipated the counterculture’s challenge to a world dominated by meaningless labour. The most politically significant figures in literature, he argued in One-Dimensional Man, were “those who don’t earn a living, at least not in an ordinary and normal way”.6 Such characters, and the forms of life with which they were associated, would come to the fore in the counterculture.
Actually, as much as Marcuse’s work was in tune with the counterculture, his analysis also forecast its ultimate failure and incorporation. A major theme of One-Dimensional Man was the neutralisation of the aesthetic challenge. Marcuse worried about the popularisation of the avant-garde, not out of elitist anxieties that the democratisation of culture would corrupt the purity of art, but because the absorption of art into the administered spaces of capitalist commerce would gloss over its incompatibility with capitalist culture. He had already seen capitalist culture convert the gangster, the beatnik and the vamp from “images another way of life” into “freaks or types of the same life”.7 The same would happen to the counterculture, many of whom, poignantly, preferred to call themselves freaks.
In any case, Marcuse allows us to see why the Sixties continue to nag at the current moment. In recent years, the Sixties have come to seem at once like a deep past so exotic and distant that we cannot imagine living in it, and a moment more vivid than now — a time when people really lived, when things really happened. Yet the decade haunts not because of some unrecoverable and unrepeatable confluence of factors, but because the potentials it materialised and began to democratise — the prospect of a life freed from drudgery — has to be continually suppressed. To explain why we have not moved to a world beyond work we have to look at a vast social, political and cultural project whose aim has been the production of scarcity. Capitalism: a system that generates artificial scarcity in order to produce real scarcity; a system that produces real scarcity in order to generate artificial scarcity. Actual scarcity — scarcity of natural resources — now haunts capital, as the Real that its fantasy of infinite expansion must work overtime to repress. The artificial scarcity — which is fundamentally a scarcity of time — is necessary, as Marcuse says, in order to distract us from the immanent possibility of freedom. (Neoliberalism’s victory, of course, depended upon a cooption of the concept of freedom. Neoliberal freedom, evidently, is not a freedom from work, but freedom through work.)
Just as Marcuse predicted, the availability of more consumer goods and devices in the global North has obscured the way in which those same goods have increasingly functioned to produce a scarcity of time. But perhaps even Marcuse could not have anticipated twenty-first-century capital’s capacity to generate overwork and to administer the time outside paid work. Maybe only a mordant futurologist like Philip K. Dick could have predicted the banal ubiquity of corporate communication today, its penetration into practically all areas of consciousness and everyday life.
“The past is so much safer”, observes one of the narrators of Margaret Atwood’s dystopian satire, The Heart Goes Last, ���because whatever’s in it has already happened. It can’t be changed: so, in a way there’s nothing to dread”.8 Despite what Atwood’s narrator thinks, the past hasn’t “already happened”. The past has to be continually re-narrated, and the political point of reactionary narratives is to suppress the potentials which still await, ready to be re-awakened, in older moments. The Sixties counterculture is now inseparable from its own simulation, and the reduction of the decade to “iconic” images, to “classic” music and to nostalgic reminiscences has neutralised the real promises that exploded then. Those aspects of the counterculture which could be appropriated have been repurposed as precursors of “the new spirit of capitalism”, while those which were incompatible with a world of overwork have been condemned as so many idle doodles, which in the contradictory logic of reaction, are simultaneously dangerous and impotent.
The subduing of the counterculture has seemed to confirm the validity of the scepticism and hostility to the kind of position Marcuse was advancing. If “the counterculture led to neoliberalism”, better that the counterculture had not happened. In fact, the opposite argument is more convincing — that the failure of the left after the Sixties had much to do with its repudiation of, or refusal to engage with, the dreamings that the counterculture unleashed. There was no inevitability about the new right’s seizure and binding of these new currents to its project of mandatory individualisation and overwork.What if the counterculture was only a stumbling beginning, rather than the best that could be hoped for?
What if the success of neoliberalism was a not an indication of the inevitability of capitalism, but a testament to the scale of the threat posed by the spectre of a society which could be free?
It is in the spirit of these questions that this book shall return to the 1960s and 1970s. The rise of capitalist realism could not happened without the narratives that reactionary forces told about those decades. Returning to those moments will allow us to continue with the process of unpicking the narratives that neoliberalism has woven around them. More importantly, it will enable the construction of new narratives.
In many ways, re-thinking the 1970s is more important than revisiting the 1960s. The 1970s was the decade that neoliberalism began a rise that it would retrospectively narrate as irresistible. However, recent work on the 1970s — including Jefferson Cowie’s Stayin’ Alive: The Last Days of the Working Class, Andy Beckett’s When the Lights Went Out and John Medhurst’s That Option No Longer Exists — has emphasised that the decade wasn’t only about the draining away of the possibilities that had exploded in the Sixties. The Seventies was a period of struggle and transition, in which the meaning and legacy of the previous decade was one of the crucial battlegrounds. Some of the emancipatory tendencies that had emerged during the Sixties intensified and proliferated during the Seventies “[F]or many politicised Britons”, Andy Beckett has written, “the decade was not the hangover after the Sixties; it was the point when the great Sixties party actually started”.9
The successful Miners’ Strike of 1972 saw an alliance between the striking miners and students that was echoed similar convergences in Paris 1968, with the miners using the University of Essex’s Colchester campus as their East Anglian base.
Moving far beyond the simple story that the “Sixties led to neoliberalism”, these new readings of the 1970s allow us to apprehend the bravura intelligence, ferocious energy and improvisational imagination of the neoliberal counter-revolution. The installation of capitalist realism was by no means a simple restoration of an old state of affairs: the mandatory individualism imposed by neoliberalism was a new form of individualism, an individualism defined against the different forms of collectivity that clamoured out of the Sixties. This new individualism was designed to both surpass and make us forget those collective forms. So to recall these multiple forms of collectivity is less an act of remembering than of unforgetting, a counter-exorcism of the spectre of a world which could be free.
Acid Communism is the name I have given to this spectre. The concept of acid communism is a provocation and a promise. It is a joke of sorts, but one with very serious purpose. It points to something that, at one point, seemed inevitable, but which now appears impossible: the convergence of class consciousness, socialist-feminist consciousness-raising and psychedelic consciousness, the fusion of new social movements with a communist project, an unprecedented aestheticisation of everyday life.
Acid communism both refers to actual historical developments and to a virtual confluence that has not yet come together in actuality. Potentials exert influence without being actualised. Actual social formations are shaped by the potential formations whose actualisation they seek to impede. The impress of “a world which could be free” can be detected in the very structures of a capitalist realist world which makes freedom impossible.
The late cultural critic Ellen Willis said that the transformations imagined by the counterculture would have required “a social and psychic revolution of almost inconceivable magnitude”.10 It’s very difficult, in our more deflated times, to re-create the counterculture’s confidence that such a “social and psychic revolution” could not only happen, but was already in the process of unfolding. But we need now to return to a time when the prospect of universal liberation seemed imminent.
No More Miserable Monday Mornings
Let’s begin with a moment that is all the more richly evocative because of its apparent modesty:
It was July 1966 and I was newly nine years old. We had holidayed on the Broads and the family had recently taken possession of the gorgeous wooden cruiser that was to be our floating home for the next fortnight. It was called The Constellation and, as my brother and I breathlessly explored the twin beds and curtained portholes in our cabin built into the boat’s bow, the prospect of what lay ahead saw the life force beaming from us like the rays of a cartoon sun. […] I […] made my way up to through the boat to take up position in the small area of the stern. On the way, I pick up sister Sharon’s teeny pink and white Sanyo transistor radio and switched it on. I looked up at the clear blue afternoon sky. Ike and Tina Turner’s “River Deep, Mountain High” was playing and a sort of rapturous trance descended on me. From the limitless blue sky I looked down into the churning, crystal-peaked wake our boat was creating as we motored along, and at that moment, “River Deep” gave way to my absolute favourite song of the period: “Bus Stop” by the Hollies. As the mock flamenco guitar flourish that marks its beginning rose above the deep burble of the Constellation’s engine, I stared into the tumbling waters and said aloud, but to myself, “This is happening now. THIS is happening now.”11
This account comes from Going To Sea in a Sieve, the memoirs of the writer and broadcaster Danny Baker. It ought to go without saying that this was nothing more than a snapshot, one sun-saturated image from a period that contained more than enough misery and horror. The Sixties were not a realised utopia, just as the opportunities that lay ahead for Baker would not be available to most working-class people. Similarly, it would be easy to discount Baker’s reverie as nostalgia for lost childhood, the kind of golden memories that practically anyone from any historical period or social background might have.
Yet there is something very specific about this moment, something that means it could have only happened then. We can enumerate some of the factors that made it unique: a sense of existential and social security that allowed working-class families to take holidays at all; the role that new technology such as transistor radios played in both connecting groups to an outside and enabling them to luxuriate in the moment, a moment that was somehow exorbitantly sufficient; the way that genuinely new music — music that wasn’t imaginable a few months never mind a few years before — could crystallise and intensify this whole scene, imbue it with a sense of casual but not complacent optimism, a sense that the world was improving.
This sense of exorbitant sufficiency could be heard in the Kinks’ “Sunny Afternoon”, which Baker might well have also heard on the same transistor radio that day, or in the Beatles’ “I’m Only Sleeping”, which would come out a month later; or in later releases like the Small Faces’ “Lazy Sunday”. These tracks apprehended the anxiety-dream toil of everyday life from a perspective that floated alongside, above or beyond it: whether it was the busy street glimpsed from the high window of a late sleeper, whose bed becomes a gently idling rowing boat; the fog and frost of a Monday morning abjured from a sunny Sunday afternoon that does not need to end; or the urgencies of business airily disdained from the eyrie of a meandering aristocratic pile, now occupied by working-class dreamers who will never clock on again.
“I’m Only Sleeping” (“stay in bed, float upstream”) was the twin of Revolver’s most self-consciously psychedelic track, “Tomorrow Never Knows” (“switch off your mind, relax and float downstream”). If the lyrics to “Tomorrow Never Knows”, minimally adapted from The Psychedelic Experience: A Manual Based on the Tibetan Book of the Dead, seem somewhat pat, the music, the sound design, retain the power to transport. “It wasn’t like anything else we’d ever heard”, John Foxx recalls of “Tomorrow Never Knows”,
but somehow seemed instantly recognisable. Sure, the words were a bit suspect, but the music, the sound — organic electricity, disintegrated transmissions, lost radio stations, Catholic/Buddhist mass from a parallel universe, what being stoned ought to be like — weightless, timeless, revelation, moving over luminous new landscapes in serene velocity. It communicated, innovated, infiltrated, fascinated, elevated — it was a road map for the future.12
These “luminous new landscapes” were worlds beyond work, where drudgery’s dreary repetitiveness gave way to drifting explorations of strange terrains. Listened to now, these tracks describe the very conditions necessary for their own production, which is to say, access to a certain mode of time, time which allows a deep absorption.
The refusal of work was also a refusal to internalise the systems of valuation which claimed that one’s existence is validated by paid employment. It was, that is to say, a refusal to submit to a bourgeois gaze which measured life in terms of success in business. “I didn’t come from a background where people had ‘careers’”, Danny Baker writes. “You went to work, you had different jobs at different times, but it was all in a jumble. It did not define you or plot your course in life — and thank God for that.” Baker left school in South East London with no qualifications. Yet he is careful that his picaresque journey from record shop assistant, to fanzine producer, music journalist and television and radio presenter should not be seen as either a hard luck nor a hard work story. He doesn’t tell it as a petit-bourgeois narrative of “betterment”, but of recklessness rewarded. This “recklessness” came out of a sense that fulfilment wasn’t to be expected from work, and from an immense confidence, which allows him to consistently rebuff bourgeois imperatives and anxieties. The two volumes of Baker’s memoirs lay out very clearly the factors which allowed this confidence to grow: the comparative stability of his father’s work, in thriving docks that seemed as if they would remain at the heart of British economic life forever; the family’s embedding in a working-class network that supplemented wages with “bunce”; its acquisition of a brand-new council flat with a garden. His own movement into writing and broadcasting was facilitated not by any entrepreneurial drive, but by a newly emerging public sphere — constituted out of parts of television, radio and print media — in which working-class perspectives were validated and valued. But this was not a working class which could be understood according to the protocols of kitchen-sink or socialist realism anymore than it was limited by ruling-class caricature. It was a working class that no longer knew its place, that had gotten above itself. Even the old redoubts of the bourgeoisie were no longer secure. In the Sixties, Ted Hughes had become one of Britain’s leading poets, Harold Pinter one of its most exciting new dramatists, both of them producing work which reflected working-class experience in challenging and difficult ways, and taking it — via television — into the living rooms of a mass audience.
In any case, we are a long way from the disappearance of class later that would later be trumpeted by neoliberal ideologues. The settlements that labour and capital had come to in societies like the US and the UK accepted that class was a permanent feature of social organisation. They assumed that there were different class interests which had to be reconciled, and that any effective, not to mention just, governance of society would have to involve the organised working class. Trade unions were strong, emboldened in their demands by low unemployment. Working-class expectations were high — gains had been made, but more were surely on the way. It was easy to imagine that the uneasy truces between capital and labour would end, not with a resurgence of the right, but with an embrace of more socialistic policies, if not quite the “full communism” that Nikita Krushchev thought would be in place by 1980. After all — or so it seemed — the right was on the backfoot, discredited and perhaps fatally damaged in the US because of the protracted and horrific failure of the Vietnam War. The “establishment” no longer commanded automatic deference; instead, it came to seem exhausted, out of touch, obsolete, limply awaiting to be washed away by any or all of the new cultural and political waves which were eroding all the old certainties.
Where the new culture was not being driven by those from working-class backgrounds, it seemed that it was being led by class renegades such as Pink Floyd, young people from bourgeois families who had rejected their own class destinies and identified “downwards”, or outwards. They wanted to do anything but go into business and banking: fields whose subsequent libidinisation would have boggled the expanded minds of the Sixties.
Working-class aspiration did not equate to class mobility, where the dubious reward was gradual and grudging acceptance by “betters”. Instead, the new bohemia seemed to point to the elimination of the bourgeoisie and its values. Indeed, it was the conviction that this was imminent which was one of the few areas of overlap between the counterculture and the traditional revolutionary left, who seemed in many other respects to be at variance with one another.
Ellen Willis certainly felt that the dominant forms of left-wing politics were incompatible with the desires and ambitions triggered and tranduced by music. While the music that she listened to spoke of freedom, socialism seemed to be about centralisation and state control. The counterculture’s politics might have been opposed to capitalism, Willis thought, but this did not entail a straightforward rejection of everything produced in the capitalist field. Her “polemic against standard leftist notions about advanced capitalism” rejected at best only half-true the ideas “that the consumer economy makes us slave to commodities, that the function of the mass media is to manipulate our fantasies, so we will equate fulfilment with buying the system’s commodities”.13 Mass culture — and music culture in particular — was a terrain of struggle rather than a dominion of capital. The relationship between aesthetic forms and politics was unstable and inchoate — aesthetic forms did not simply “express” some already-existing capitalist reality, they anticipated and actually produced new possibilities. Commodification was not the point at which this tension would always and inevitably be resolved in favour of capital; rather, commodities could themselves be the means by which rebellious currents could propagate:
the mass media helped to spread rebellion, and the system obligingly marketed products that encouraged it, for the simple reason that there was money to be made from rebels who were also consumers. On one level the sixties revolt was an impressive illustration of Lenin’s remark that the capitalist will sell you the rope to hang him with.14
In the UK, Stuart Hall felt similar frustrations with much of the existing left — frustrations that were all the more intense in his case because he thought of himself as a socialist. But the socialism that Hall wanted — a socialism that could engage with the yearnings and dreamings that he heard in Miles Davis’ music — was yet to be created, and its arrival was obstructed as much by figures from the left as from the right.
The first obstructive figure of the left was the complacent steward of Cold War organised labour or social democracy: backward-looking, bureaucratic, resigned to the “inevitability” of capitalism, more interested in preserving the income and status of white men than in expanding the struggle to include…, this figure is defined by compromise and eventual failure.The other figure — what I want to call the Harsh Leninist Superego — is defined by its absolute refusal of compromise. According to Freud, the superego is characterised by the quantitatively and qualitatively excessive nature of its demands: whatever we do, it’s never enough. The Harsh Leninist Superego mandates a militant ascesis. The militant will be single-mindedly dedicated to the revolutionary event, and unflinchingly committed to the means necessary to bring it about. The Harsh Leninist Superego is as indifferent to suffering as it is hostile to pleasure Lenin’s phobic response to music is instructive here: “I can’t listen to music too often. It affects your nerves, makes you want to say stupid nice things and stroke the heads of people who could create such beauty while living in this vile hell.”
While the complacent leaders of organised labour were invested in the status quo, the Harsh Leninist Superego stakes everything on a world absolutely different to this one. It was this post-revolutionary world which would redeem the Leninist, and it was from the perspective of this world that they judged themselves. In the meantime, it is legitimate and indeed necessary to cultivate an indifference towards current suffering: we can and must step over homeless people, because giving to charity only obstructs the coming of the revolution.
But this revolution had little in common with the “social and psychic revolution of almost inconceivable magnitude” that Ellen Willis thought was seeded in the counterculture’s dreamings. The revolution as she conceived of it would at once be more immediate — it would fundamentally concern how care and domestic arrangements were organised — and more far-reaching: the transformed world would be unimaginably stranger than anything Marxist-Leninism had projected. The counterculture thought it was already producing spaces where this revolution could already be experienced.
To get some sense of what those spaces were like, we can do no better than listen to the Tempations’ “Psychedelic Shack”, released in December 1969. The group play the role of breathless ingénues who have just returned from some kind of Wonderland: “Strobe lights flashin’ way till after sundown… There ain’t no such thing as time… Incense in the air…”
youtube
For all the familiarity of these signifiers, listening to “Psychedelic Shack” now can actually bring us up short. Invited to think about the psychedelic, our first associations might be with solipsistic withdrawal (the lyrics of a track like “Tomorrow Never Knows” invite just such an association). Yet “Psychedelic Shack” describes a space that is very definitely collective, that bustles with all the energy of a bazaar. For all its carnivalesque departures from everyday reality, however, this is no remote utopia. It feels like an actual social space, one you can imagine really existing. You are as likely to come upon a crank or a huckster as a poet or musician here, and who knows if today’s crank might turn out to be tomorrow’s genius? It is also an egalitarian and democratic space, and a certain affect presides over everything. There is multiplicity, but little sign of resentment or malice. It is a space for fellowship, for meeting and talking as much for having your mind blown. If “there’s no such thing as time” — because the lighting suspends the distinction between day and night; because drugs affect time-perception — then you are not prey to the urgencies which make so much of workaday life a drudge. There is no limit to how long conversations can last, and no telling where encounters might lead. You are free to leave your street identity behind, you can transform yourself according to your desires, according to desires which you didn’t know you had.
The crucial defining feature of the psychedelic is the question of consciousness, and its relationship to what is experienced as reality. If the very fundamentals of our experience, such as our sense of space and time, can be altered, does that not mean that the categories by which we live are plastic, mutable? Understood in individual terms, this quickly leads to the facile relativism and a naïve voluntarism that the Temptations themselves had targeted on their first psychedelic soul single, “Cloud Nine”. Sure, you can be what you want to be, but only by being a million miles from reality, only by leaving behind all your responsibilities. This superegoic appeal could have been endorsed by conservatives as well as a certain brand of radical: conservatives, who wanted everyone to knuckle down to work; militants, who demanded commitment to revolution, which — they said — entailed an attention to the horrors of the world, not a quick fix flight from the real.
Yet the claim that altered states of consciousness took you a “million miles away from reality” was question-begging. It foreclosed the idea that altered state of consciousness could offer a perception of the systems of power, exploitation and ritual that was more, not less, lucid than ordinary consciousness. In the Sixties, when consciousness was increasingly besieged by the fantasies and images of advertising and capitalist spectacle, how solid was the “reality” from which psychedelic states fled in any case? Wasn’t the state of consciousness susceptible to spectacle more like somnambulance than alertness or awareness?
In retrospect, one of the most remarkable features of the psychedelic culture of the 1960s was the way it mainstreamed such metaphysical questions. The psychedelic was not new — many pre-capitalist societies had incorporated psychedelic visions and the use of hallucinogens into their ritual practice. What was new was the break out of the psychedelic from particular ritualised spaces and times, and from the control of particular practitioners, such as shamans and sorcerers. Experiments with consciousness were now in principle open to anyone. Despite all the mysticism and pseudo-spiritualism which has always hung over psychedelic culture, there was actually a demystificatory and materialist dimension to this. Widespread experiments with consciousness promised nothing less than a democratisation of neurology itself — a newly widespread awareness of the brain’s role in producing what was experienced as reality. Those on acid trips were externalising the workings of their own brain, and potentially learning to use their brains differently.
Yet psychedelic experiences were not confined to those who had taken drugs. The very mass media which mainstreamed psychedelic concepts along with the Vietnam War was itself a massive experiment in altering consciousness. With television, the breakdown of the distinction between dreams and waking life that film had begun now entered “private” domestic space. Television was at the centre of a media landscape that was still only just assembling, and which no one understood because nothing like it had ever existed before. The Beatles released their first album only a few months before the assassination of John F. Kennedy. Television was channel for contagion (Beatlemania!), trauma and hysteria as much as paternalistic messages or commercial huckstering. No one had been as famous in their own lifetime as the Beatles, because the infrastructure for such a fame was only just being created, and the Beatles themselves were playing a part in building it, as if — at one and the same time — the world had become an extension of their own electronic dream, and they had become characters in everyone else’s dream.
You might say that the Beatles’ own psychedelic turn was an attempt to convert all of this into a lucid dream. This is the quality of Sgt Pepper’s “A Day in the Life”, which plays out the difference between Lennon’s lucid dream calm and the urgencies of work life (McCartney’s breathless commuter, who reaches the bus in seconds flat). Yet escape from urgencies is always achingly proximate — once on the bus, McCartney’s immediately character falls into a dream.
Lennon sounds dispassionate but not detached; there is humour but no blokish familiarity. His vocal seems to intimate that the ordinary somnambulance of the workaday world can only be properly apprehended from the perspective afforded by a different kind of trance. Or is it, rather, that a voice disconnected from the imperatives of working/waking life comes off as catatonic? The tracks shows us the inside seen from outside, as Lennon takes us on journey through the different ways in which consciousness is electronically mediated (by newspapers, film, television): “I read the news today, oh boy”.
This contrast between urgency and lucidity was everywhere in Jonathan Miller’s television adaptation of Alice’s Adventures in Wonderland. It was broadcast on BBC television in December 1966, and reflected the influence of the Beatles even as it would go on to influence the Beatles in turn. Shot in black and white, the film has a strangely sober, almost austere visual style, devoid of any special effects or florid imagery. This fits with the adaptation’s most striking innovation, its rendering of the characters not as animals, but as human beings. “Once you take the animal heads off”, Miller told Life, “you begin to see what it’s all about. A small child, surrounded by hurrying, worried people, thinking: ‘is this what being grown up is like?’”
The film is pervaded by an atmosphere of lassitude, of languor and catatonia that sometimes lurches into sudden panic and helplessness. Miller again: “The book, by dressing things up in animal clothes, presents a disguised — a dream-disguised — domestic charade. […] All the levels of authority and order-giving and obedience are reflected.”15 The ordinary world appears as a tissue of Nonsense, incomprehensibly inconsistent, arbitrary and authoritarian, dominated by bizarre rituals, repetitions and automatisms. It is itself a bad dream, a kind of trance. In the solemn and autistic testiness of the adults who torment and perplex Alice, we see the madness of ideology itself: a dreamwork that has forgotten it is a dream, and which seeks to make us forget too, by sweeping us up in its urgencies, by perplexing us with its lugubrious dementia, or by terrifying us with its sudden, unpredictable and insatiable violence.
The laugher that this Alice provokes — sometimes uneasy, sometimes uproarious — is a laughter that comes from the outside. It is a psychedelic laughter, a laughter that — far from confirming or validating the values of any status quo — exposes the bizarreness, the inconsistency, of what had been taken for common sense. Is this not the laugher that Michel Foucault describes in a justly renowned passage from the Preface to The Order of Things, a book that was originally published in the same year that Miller’s version of Alice was broadcast? Foucault refers there to a story by Borges in which
he quotes a ‘certain Chinese encyclopaedia’ in which it is written that “animals are divided into: (a) belonging to the Emperor, (b) embalmed, (c) tame, (d) suckling pigs, (e) sirens, (f) fabulous, (g) stray dogs, (h) included in the present classification, (i) frenzied, (j) innumerable, (k) drawn with a very fine camelhair brush, (l) et cetera, (m) having just broken the water pitcher, (n) that from a long way off look like flies”. In the wonderment of this taxonomy, the thing we apprehend in one great leap, the thing that, by means of the fable, is demonstrated as the exotic charm of another system of thought, is the limitation of our own, the stark impossibility of thinking that.16
This perspective, this laughter from the outside, runs through all Foucault’s work. For all its intricacy, its density and opacity, Foucault’s major work from The History of Madness at the beginning of the 1960s, in the… through to the books on sexuality he would publish after the Death Valley seem to revolve around and repeat a fundamental insight, or outsight. … the arbitrariness and contingency of any system, its plasticity.
If this outside vision was consonant with the psychedelic consciousness, in Foucault’s case it did not have its origins in drugs. Foucault wouldn’t consume LSD until nearly a decade later, when he headed out to Death Valley and took acid at Zabriskie Point, the site of Michelangelo Antonioni’s film about the counterculture.
Foucault, seldom comfortable in his own skin, was always looking for a way out of his own identity. He had memorably claimed that he wrote “in order not to have a face”, and his prodigious exercises in rogue scholarship and conceptual invention, the textual labyrinths he meticulously assembled from innumerable historical and philosophical sources, were one way out of the face. Another route was what he called the limit-experience, one version of which was his encounter with LSD. The limit-experience was paradoxical: it was an experience at and beyond the limits of “ordinary” experience, an experience of what cannot ordinarily be experienced at all. The limit-experience offered a kind of metaphysical hack. The conditions which made ordinary experience possible could now be encountered, transformed and escaped — at least temporarily. Yet, by definition, the entity which underwent this could not be the ordinary subject of experience — it would instead be some anonymous X, a faceless being.
Much of the music that came out of the counterculture gave voice to this entity from the outside, and Foucault’s turn to the limit-experience paralleled popular experimentations with consciousness. “[T]he problem”, Foucault said, in one of the interviews collected in the book Remarks on Marx,
is not to recover our “lost” identity, to free our imprisoned nature, our deepest truth; but instead, the problem is to move towards something radically Other. The center, then, seems still to be found in Marx’s phrase: man produces man. […] For me, what must be produced is not man identical to himself, exactly as nature would have designed him or according to his essence; on the contrary, we must produce something that doesn’t yet exist and about which we cannot know how and what it will be.17
In a commentary on Foucault’s text, Michael Hardt has argued that “the positive content of communism, which corresponds to the abolition of private property, is the autonomous production of humanity — a new seeing, a new hearing, a new thinking, a new loving.”18
A new humanity, a new seeing, a new thinking, a new loving: this is the promise of acid communism, and it was the promise that you could hear in “Psychedelic Shack” and the culture that inspired it. Only five years separated “Psychedelic Shack” from the Tempations’ early signature hit “My Girl”, but how many new worlds had come into being then? In “My Girl”, love remains sentimentalised, confined to the couple, in “Psychedelic Shack”, love is collective, and orientated towards the outside.
With “Psychedelic Shack”, the Temptations were a year into the new sound that the group’s unofficial leader, Otis Williams, had persuaded producer Norman Whitfield to develop. Whitfield had initially been reluctant to change the Temptations’ sound but his eventual conversion would lead to some of the most stunning productions in popular music history: productions that would build on the promise that “Tomorrow Never Knows” evoked, but which the Beatles themselves would rarely make good on. Whitfield became so entranced by the psychedelic soundscapes he worked on in the studio that he would push for The Temptations to release tracks that were eight or nine minutes long, with space for extended instrumental passages. He formed the group the Undisputed Truth specifically as a lab to try out these long-form lysergic productions. Whitfield’s experimentation with the studio as a compositional tool paralleled what Lee “Scratch” Perry was doing in Jamaica with dub. The sonic spaces they opened up were also about a particular experience of time: a distended time, a time that was at once denuded, and populated with strange audio unlike forms, which enticed the listener into a deep immersion in the moment, even as they enfolded us into rhythmic patterns and pulses. This new space-time would later be revisited and refurbished by new explorers such as Tom Moulton, Larry Levan and Walter Gibbons: the inventors of the extended dance track, which would in turn form the basis of the psychedelic genres such as house, techno and jungle.
The template for the new Temptations’ sound had been Sly and the Family Stone, with traces of James Brown and Jimi Hendrix: a febrile matrix, composed of elements which were already interacting with one another. The change in sound was more than a shift in style; it was also responded to a new set of demands and expectations of what music could be. No longer confined to love-song balladeering or good-time cheerleading, popular music could now be social comment; even better, it could feed off and feed back into the social transformations that were dissolving former certainties, prejudices, assumptions. It could take its bearings from the confidence, anger and assertiveness that was brimming out of the Civil Rights movement, and it could perform a new set of social relations that gave a heady taste of what the world might look like once the movement had succeeded. That is what Greil Marcus heard and saw in Sly and the Family Stone in his great 1975 essay, “The Myth of Staggerlee”:
Sly’s real triumph was that he had it both ways. Every nuance of his style, from the razzle dazzle of his threads to the originality of his music, made it clear that we was his own man. If the essence of his music was freedom, no one was more aggressively free than he. Yet there was also room for everyone in the America made up of blacks and whites, men and women, who sang out “different strokes for different folks” and were there on stage to show what such an idea of independence meant.19
Sly and the Family Stone did indeed seem to have it every way: with a sound that was somehow ramshackle, improvised, and yet sinuously danceable; a music that was neither sentimental, nor sanctimonious, but humorous and deadly serious all at the same time.
The laughter of Alice, the ludic freedom and daring embodied by Sly and the Family Stone: they might have been performed by an advanced guard, but there was no necessity for them to be confined to an elite. On the contrary, the question that their presence on radio and TV insistently posed was: why shouldn’t this bohemia be open to everyone?
Despite much of the traditional left’s deafness and hostility to these currents, the counterculture did have an impact on the workplace, in struggles conducted by a new kind of worker. “It’s a different generation of workingmen”, explained J.D. Smith, a union treasurer at the Chevy Vega plant in Lordstown, Ohio. “None of these guys came over from the old country, grateful for any job they could get. None of them have been through a depression. They’ve been exposed — at least through television — to all the youth movements of the last ten years and they don’t see the disgrace of being unemployed.”20
In 1972, the Lordstown Plant was embroiled in a struggle over working conditions which reflected the new intolerance towards drudgery and authoritarianism. “The Lordstown workers”, Jefferson Cowie writes,
became a collective national symbol for the new breed of worker and emblematic of a widespread sense of occupational alienation. People gravitated to the refreshing vision of youth, vitality, inter-racial solidarity hidden from the public behind the likes of television’s Archie Bunker, prowar labor leadership, and the growing politics of the blue-collar backlash.21
Lordstown was part of a wave of activism in which this “new breed of worker” struggled for democratic control of their own trade unions and of the places in which they worked. Seen in the light of such struggles, the egalitarian social space projected in “Psychedelic Shack” could not be dismissed as a passive pipe-dream or a distraction from actual political activity. Rather, music such as this was an active dreaming which arose out of real social and cultural compositions, and which fed back into potent new collectivities, and a new existential atmosphere, which rejected both drudgery and traditional resentments. “The young black and white workers dig each other”, said the Lordstown Local president Gary Bryner, “There’s an understanding. The guy with the Afro, the guy with the beads, the guy with the goatee, he doesn’t care if he’s black, white, green or yellow.” These new kinds of workers — who “smoked dope, socialised interracially, and dreamed of a world in which work had some meaning”22 — wanted democratic control of both their workplace and their trade unions.
Something of the same ferment was building in Italy, where a new kind of worker was increasingly visible. “This new generation of workers did not have so much to do with the old tradition of the labor parties”, says Franco Berardi of the situation in Turin in 1973. “Nor anything to do with the socialist ideology of a state-owned system. A massive refusal of the sadness of work was the leading element behind their protest. Those young workers had much more to do with the hippy movement; much more to do with the history of the avant-garde.”23
By 1977, a whole new social mix, a “mass avant-garde”, was in place in Bologna. It was here, perhaps more than anywhere else, that acid communism came together as an actual formation. The city seethed with the energy and confidence that erupts when new ideas commingle with new aesthetic forms.
The university was filled with terroni (people originating from the South), Germans, comedians, musicians and cartoonists like Andrea Pazienza and Filippo Scozzari. Artists were squatting houses in the center of the city, and running creative places such as Radio Alice and Traumfabrik. Some people were reading books like Anti-Oedipus, some were reciting poems by Majakovski and Artaud, listening to the music of Keith Jarrett and The Ramones, and inhaling dream inducing substances.24
As In February, A/traverso, the zine published by Berardi and others young militants, produced an issue entitled “The revolution is just, possible and necessary: look comrades, the revolution is probable”:
We want to expropriate all the assets of the Catholic Church
Cut the working hours, increase the number of jobs
Increase the amount of the salary
Transform production and place it under workers’ control
Liberation of the huge amount of intelligence that is wasted by capitalism: Technology has been used so far as a means of control and exploitation.
It wants to be turned into a tool for liberation.
Working less is possible thanks to the application of cybernetics and informatics.
Zerowork for income
Automate all production
All power to living labor
All work to dead labor.
In 1977, such demands seemed not only realistic but inevitable — “look comrades, the revolution is probable”. Of course, we now know that the revolution did not happen. But the material conditions for such a revolution are more in place in the twenty-first century than they were in 1977. What has shifted beyond all recognition since then is the existential and emotional atmosphere. Populations are resigned to the sadness of work, even as they are told that automation is making their jobs disappear. We must regain the optimism of that Seventies moment, just as we must carefully analyse all the machineries that capital deployed to convert confidence into dejection. Understanding how this process of consciousness-deflation worked is the first step to reversing it.
--------------------------- The End ---------------------------
last chapter, in: K-Punk: The Collected and Unpublished Writings of Mark Fisher (2004-2016)
0 notes
Video
youtube
Lecture - N.T. Wright - How Paul Invented Christian Theology
COMMENTARY:
YliyahMessageTime
It is impossible to sort out what you are talking about except that you believe that spelling "Israel" as "Israyl" somehow represents a compelling argument. Among other things, your commentary is hopelessly anachronological, confusing the Rome of pre-Nicea with the Rome of the present day Catholic Church. You've obviously worked yourself up into a theological lather and, if this was Palestine circa 33 or even 59, you would probably be lumped in with John the Baptist as a prophet of apocalpse. Unfortunately, nothing you present offers a lifting of the veil in any manner nor clarification of the events before 70.
My premise is that Cornelius is the author of the Gospel of Mark and that it, Mark, is at least the second iteration of intelligence coming out of Palestine to the "Christian" desk of the Praetorian Guard since His Resurrection, a possibility not even in the realm of practical mythology of the Roman world view. The first iteration of intelligence regarding Resurrection compelled Tiberius to propose Jesus as a legal deity sometime between 33 and Tiberius' death in 37. The term "Christian", which is clearly an invention of the Roman soldiers dealing with this emerging Jewish movement, was introduced to Rome at this time and eventually migrated naturally to the rest of the Empire, including Antioch, by 45 or so.
The Gospel of Mark, composed by Cornelius, is, essentially, anthropological journalism assembled from the Roman military intelligence archives, the testimony of Peter and the eyewitness accounts of Jesus' activities largely collected before He was even arrested, much less Resurrected. Mark was composed in Latin and forwarded to the Praetorian Guard in Rome immediately after, and as a result of, the debriefing of Peter described in Acts 10 in 40. There is very little interpretation of the Jewish culture in Mark, with the exception of the aborgation of all things kosher in Mark 7 and, even then, the full significance is not reflected in the general text, but expanded upon in the parenthetical clause in Mark 7:19, which was added to later manuscripts. Cornelius had an on-going relationship with the Capernaum synagogue, and its president Jarius, but as a God Fearer from outside the boundaries of the Jewish culture. Cornelius was a very skilled observer and intelligence officer, but reporting an alien milieu. He captured all the dots, but it took Matthew Levi to connect the dots as part of his polemic supporting the Judaizers opposing Paul's wholesale inclusion of pagans into the Christian community.
Luke/Acts is a further iteration of this basic intelligence construct. It was commissioned by Theophilus, a Roman of equestrian rank, as an expansion of the portrait drawn by Cornelius of Jesus and as an explication of Paul's Letter to the Romans. Romans is basically a legal argument detailing the continuity of the emerging Christian community, and its doctrines, with the Jewish scriptures and traditions in order to convey the privileges of worship Israel enjoyed with Rome to the Christians. Paul apparently defends Romans to the Praetorian Guard to his satisfaction as reflected in Philippians 1:13 and that defense represents the essential task of his missionary after his conversion on the road to Damascus. Paul's career from that point, forward, becomes moot to the larger purpose of the sowing of The Word: getting his argument to Rome was his singular imperative, the evangelism and establishment of churches part of the laboratory of his emergent theology as pointed out in this video.
Hebrews was written by a highly educated Roman, very likely Theophilus, who has studied the Jewish scriptures and traditions extensively before its composition, somewhere around the beginning of Nero's persecutions (as can be inferred from the text) and at the same time Revelation is being composed on Patmos. Although it pays its respects to the arc of the Jewish narrative in the Torah and subsequent library, as the context from which Jesus emerges, Hebrews traces the epistemological and ethical threads from before Israel and to Melchizedek as the common source for both the Law of Moses and the emergence of the Roman secular rule of law. Melchizedek apparently influence everyone around the Mediterranean, including the Greeks and Carthage, Rome was developing its Republic 300 years before Plato issued his monologue on the subject, but the Greeks had begun the shift from the Aesthetic of the Heroic Age as the organizing principle of society to the Ethic of democratic Athens, which is the battle Socrates picks to fight with hemlock in 399, at which time Rome was already employing the republican structures for secular government which would convey via John Knox's Book of Discipline and Federalist 10 to the US Constitution. And this all starts, from the Roman perspective reflected in Hebrews before Moses had a jock strap with Melchizedek. I mean, the essential theme of Hebrews is that Christianity is the best of all religions, with Judaism the beta test model.
In fact, it is useful to consider Hebrews as an exhortation similar to Henry V at Agincort, urging the Jewish Christians to double-down on their religious displays just at the moment Nero would make that an especially dangerous policy. The evidence from Mark and Luke/Acts is that the Roman association with Jesus before His resurrection is largely photoshopped out, Matthew being the exception requiring Roman confirmation for Jewish Christian conversion.
It is apparent that Christianity had gone viral in the Roman legions, albeit covertly, by the time the X Legion encamped in Gethsemane in 69 and 70 and the author of Hebrews, a member of the Italian Christian community mentioned in Hebrews 13:24, which are the Praetorian Guards, was a part of that covert movement and wanted to keep it that way and was conjoling the Jewish Christians to be the diversionary force in the progress of the Christian agenda.
By the time of Milvian Bridge, there is a critical mass of Christians in both armies. Constantine's employment of XP served as a force multiplier for his soldiers while it discouraged and disorganized Maxentius' army. Hebrews probably served as a staff finding for Constantine in his decision to adopt Christianity as the state Church and informed his formation of, and contribution to, the Council of Nicea. At this point, you can begin complaining about the Catholic Church, but not before. And, by this time, Christianity is purely a Roman construct, the imperatives of Temple Judaism with its sacrificial blood motif, having been plowed under with Jerusalem in 70. Constantine's only mistake at this point was to dismantle the Praetorian Guard and adopting the decadent structures of a theocracy.
But, in regards to your "Israyl" enthusiasms, they are mostly your own heresies.
0 notes
Text
Climate Change Denial as the Historical Consciousness of Trumpism: Lessons from Carl Schmitt
Of all the errors made today by liberals—I use the term broadly—our most fundamental has been our underestimation of Trumpism as a philosophical movement.
We have no trouble loathing Donald Trump the man. His temperament and political impulses are self-evidently those of an authoritarian, straight from the pages of Adorno or Hayek. Likewise, our criticism of his administration’s misguided policies has been ever at the ready.
Yet to say of President Trump and his followers that they hold or are even capable of holding philosophical convictions is generally to invite ridicule, as if the term were an undeserved appellation of grace. Trump doesn’t philosophize, he tweets.
Understandable though this tendency is, it is mistaken and self-defeating. Indeed, it is a signal of our own intellectual weakness. And if we continue, it will redound to our detriment by hindering our ability to reinvigorate liberal principles for our own time.
Trumpism is well on the road to becoming a systematic program of ideas that will carefully refine its views through praxis and—allied with anti-liberal movements elsewhere in the world, especially in Russia—articulate a new, fundamental challenge to liberal thought for the twenty-first century.
As this transformation takes place, liberals should be ready. We need to understand Trumpism as a philosophical movement even better than its own adherents do, and with full interpretive sympathy, and we need to be prepared to confront it along all its philosophical axes.
The most central of these axes is Trumpism’s approach to history, because the identity of a political movement, like that of a nation, becomes fully apparent only once it possesses a self-conscious understanding of the past.
That was the case for Marxism. And for liberalism (or here). And it will be the case for Trumpism.
True to politics in the digital age, however, Trumpian historical consciousness will appear in new guises and unexpected forms.
***
There are many types of historical consciousness under Trumpism, variously supporting each other and competing for dominance.
History as heritage and nostalgia—#MAGA. History as reverence and fidelity—Straussianism and constitutional originalism. History as a philosophy of action—embodied in the novels of Trump’s intellectual precursor, Newt Gingrich. History as racial melancholy—Charlottesville. History as a resource of trans-historical Germanic mythology—the masculinist branches of the alt-right. History as conspiracy—Infowars, #fakenews, and the “rigged” political system. History as providence and decay—the implicit revival of Jacksonian-era romantic nationalism, with its narrative scaffolding of dwindling popular sovereignty.
And then there’s Stephen Bannon’s philosophy of generational change, about which I’ve written elsewhere, a toxic blend of Toynbee and Jung—history as a cycle of apocalypse and renewal.
Here I’d like to offer some thoughts about an especially significant type of Trumpian historical consciousness: climate change denial.
We naturally tend to understand climate change denial as part of a larger struggle over the respect accorded to scientific data in the making of public policy—and it is that. But stripped of its meteorological content and considered formally, climate change denial also is a view about the meaning of events as they unfold over time.
It’s a view about the history of the environment.
This very expensive GLOBAL WARMING bullshit has got to stop. Our planet is freezing, record low temps,and our GW scientists are stuck in ice
— Donald J. Trump (@realDonaldTrump) January 2, 2014
I’m not concerned with the anti-scientific character of climate change denial, at least not primarily. Instead, I’d like to suggest that it plays a significant role in the architecture of Trumpism as a developing philosophical system.
As a framework for interpreting the past, climate change denial grows logically from the core metaphysical commitments of contemporary populist nationalism in its confrontation with trans-Atlantic, cosmopolitan, individualist liberalism.
In this respect one might thus regard it as the distinctive form of anti-liberal historical thinking of our era.
This means that it also offers the greatest opportunity for liberals to address some of our own philosophical failings.
***
To understand the philosophical significance of climate change denial for Trumpism, it’s helpful to turn to the work of a thinker whose writings, it’s been suggested (and here), underwrite the movement’s “intellectual source code”: the German constitutional theorist Carl Schmitt (1888-1985).
For readers acquainted with Schmitt, the outlines of the emerging political philosophy of Trumpism seem eerily familiar. Over the course of his campaign and presidency, Trump has consistently expressed in action principles that Schmitt developed at the level of theory.
On Schmitt’s view, liberal states are weak and vulnerable, subject to corrosion from within—through capture by private interest groups—and conquest from abroad. In the American case, as Trump would have it, the United States has been “crippled” and reduced to “carnage” by self-interested financial and cultural elites, radical Islamic terrorists, cunning foreign trade negotiators, and illegal immigrants from Mexico.
The source of this vulnerability, Schmitt argues, is modern liberalism’s thin conception of political community and the state. Because liberals misunderstand the very nature of political life, they create conditions under which their nations implode.
According to Schmitt, a political community arises when its members coalesce around some aspect of their common existence. On this basis, they distinguish between their “friends” and “enemies,” the latter of whom they are ultimately prepared to fight and kill to defend their way of life.
A political community, that is, is created through an animating sense of common identity and existential threat—indeed, that’s how “the political” as a fundamental sphere of human value comes into being, and how it provides the cultural foundation of sovereignty and the state for a community of equals.
Schmitt believes that this pugilistic view of politics rings true as a conceptual matter, but he also regards drawing the friend-enemy distinction as a quasi-theological duty and part of what it means to be fully human.
Without the friend-enemy distinction, he argues, political life would vanish, and without it something essential to humanity would vanish, too—human existence would be reduced to mere private hedonism. This gives Schmittianism, like the Bannon-affiliated elements of Trumpism, a family affinity to traditionalism in Russia—a link highlighted by Bannon’s discussion of the traditionalist underpinnings of Eurasianism in his 2014 remarks to a gathering of the Human Dignity Institute.
One could equally express the Schmittian worldview in more theologically positive terms, as I’ve discussed elsewhere, as a politics based on love. For Schmitt, the political is founded on the essential mutual regard of community members for what they share beneath their surface-level differences. That recognition justifies the state’s demand that citizens be prepared to make the ultimate sacrifice in its name, and for Schmitt it forms the philosophical precondition of law itself.
***
Two principles of Schmitt’s writing are especially relevant to understanding the place of climate change denial in Trumpism’s historical consciousness, and they’re worth discussing at some length. Each principle links Trumpian domestic and international politics as two sides of the same philosophical coin.
The political is inviolable
First, for Schmitt a community’s ability to draw the friend-enemy distinction can—by definition—brook no conceptual or institutional restraint.
Most notably, the distinction can’t be predicated on other domains of human value, such as morals, aesthetics, or economics. Ideals from these fields may be used to enhance public feelings of opposition. Enemies are regularly portrayed as ugly, for instance—a practice at which Trump personally excels.
But the object of a community’s political dissociation is made on the basis of criteria independent from judgments about good and evil, beauty and ugliness, or profit and loss.
Liberals today regularly violate this principle. They seek to circumscribe national sovereignty within generally-applicable legal norms such as individual human dignity—consider Article I of the German Basic Law—and to restrict it through institutions like the United Nations.
Schmitt views such liberal projects not simply as naïve, but also as a recipe for social chaos at home and unrestrained, imperialistic violence abroad.
On the domestic level, according to Schmitt, when liberals predicate the friend-enemy distinction on ideals drawn from other value domains, they undermine the state by confusing their community’s own self-understanding. Who are we if our state holds basic responsibilities to everyone?
Such uncertainty chips away at what President Trump, warning specifically about the fate of the West, described as a community’s “will to survive.” It also leaves the state vulnerable to capture and abuse by self-interested private groups, because its essential duties and commitments become unclear.
Trump’s repeated insistence that “I will never, ever let you down” expresses the underlying Trumpian belief that, in Schmittian terms, liberal representatives from both parties have lost sight of the friend-enemy distinction that lies at the core of the nation’s existence.
According to Schmitt, a parallel problem exists on the international stage. In his view, the liberal effort to circumscribe national sovereignty within universalist legal and moral criteria increases the possibility of total war.
By moralizing conflict, liberals become disinclined to make deals with their opponents to limit war’s scope. They transform “conventional” enemies into “absolute” enemies, against whom fighting can never truly cease.
They also seek to reconstruct other societies in their own image—after all, they base their own political identity on universalistic criteria.
Trump acts in full accord with Schmitt in this respect by praising Vladimir Putin and embracing autocratic Russia as a potential friend while snubbing liberal nations of the trans-Atlantic alliance. In fact, one would expect such a realignment from a sovereign unshackling itself from decades of liberal universalism.
On the Schmittian view, a people in no way acts inconsistently or improperly if it determines that another political entity is its existential “friend” although it engages in practices that violate the people’s basic views of right and wrong.
Great move on delay (by V. Putin) – I always knew he was very smart!
— Donald J. Trump (@realDonaldTrump) December 30, 2016
Trump is likewise consistent with Schmitt in insisting that the American goal in Afghanistan should be “killing terrorists”—”not nation building.”
Both Schmittianism and Trumpism possess a striking normative pluralism.
The political requires territorialization
The relation between politics and geography is the second aspect of Schmitt’s philosophy that’s relevant to thinking about climate change.
In Schmitt’s view the state, as the bearer of a people’s sovereignty, must create clear territorial boundaries that correspond to its friend-enemy distinction. If the territory of a state doesn’t track the distinction between friend and enemy, then the identity of its underlying political community becomes muddled. This process mirrors spatially the confusion that results when liberals seek to circumscribe sovereignty conceptually.
For Schmitt, that’s why states also should seek to homogenize the political community within their borders, and why the “sovereign dictator”—a leader exercising power in a period of constitutional transition—should quash internal dissent.
Accordingly, at the heart of Trump’s campaign was the promise to territorialize the friend-enemy distinction, namely to build a “great wall” along the border between the United States and Mexico—a promise that became his movement’s most fervent rallying cry: “Build the wall!”
The cry is Schmittian in two respects, one obvious, the other less so.
Most obviously, it expresses the Schmittian position that a community’s political obligations should be physically legible. A border wall is a fitting architectural symbol of a Schmittian conception of the state—indeed, Schmitt himself once explained that the normative order of a people “can be described as a wall.”
Jeb Bush just talked about my border proposal to build a “fence.” It’s not a fence, Jeb, it’s a WALL, and there’s a BIG difference!
— Donald J. Trump (@realDonaldTrump) August 25, 2015
In addition, the Schmittian quality of the slogan is implicit in the spirit with which it typically has been chanted at rallies
0 notes
Photo
Religion, Things, Idea, Sensation (Reading Max Müller)
In putting together the syllabus for my graduate seminar, I decided to add the almost but never quite long forgotten Max Müller to his rightful place in the canon of classical theories and methods in the study of Religion. I did so because I find him interesting, undoubtedly in spite of himself, and also for colleagues and students in the department working on the religions of India; and for one senior colleague who adores him. We read Lectures on the Origin and Growth of Religion as Illustrated by the Religions of India (1878), which you can find here in its entirety. I chose this one because of its focus on Vedic sources and then Vedantic philosophy as the foundation upon which to build a theory of Religion. The title and project, although not the method, reminded me of Hermann Cohen’s Religion of Reason out of the Sources of Judaism.
Class discussion included, but got bogged down on colonialism and liberal humanism. This was bound to happen, and we needed to get that leg of the larger conversation out on the table. In the book’s concluding “Retrospect,” inelegantly lumped on at the end of the last substantive chapter, Müller describes himself going into the crypt, devoting himself to ancient wisdom and world religions, crowned rhetorically by Christianity. It suggests very much the critique leveled against the obsession with origins that one finds in Müller him and other founding theorists of religion leveled by Tomaoko Masuzawa in In Search of Dreamtime. Reflecting and orienting the self-consciously anxious subject-position of the modern western subject, the study of religions is viewed by Müller as creating a place of refuge in the busy, noisy, contentious modern world.
Müller’s is a Protestant theory of religion out of the Vedic Sources, in which religion is defined in relation to the human apprehension of “The Infinite.” Representing a late gesture in the German Idealist tradition, this centrality of the infinite is hardly the most interesting part of the theory. The more abiding point of interest is the attention given by Müller, the first translator into English of Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, the ordinary, sensual root of that apprehension in relation to ideas and language.
Müller designed a theological interpretation of religion that has been rejected out of hand by our caustic friends over at the North American Association for the Study of Religion (NASSR). These are the critics in the field rejecting out of hand any and all claims that religion represents a uniquely privileged phenomenon distinct and set apart (sanctified) from historical, social, and political contexts. In his defense, I would start by noting that Müller refuses all appeals to special revelation or to a special mental faculty or receptivity to the signals of religious phenomena. For Müller, the starting point of religion is ordinary perception in relation to Nature, a point of view rejected by Durkheim as “naturism.” While there is much that might be right and wrong about the theory, at the very least it does not treat religion as sui generis.
Lost in the classroom discussion was the way objects figure in Müller’s theory of religion. Against Positivists who argue that human experience is limited to finite experience, he located the apprehension of the infinite in the ordinary experience with tangible, semi-tangible, and intangible objects. This classification is the heart of the book. The semi-tangible would be that object that one cannot pick up in the hand or view in a single intuition. In contrast, tangible objects (which Müller most likely identified with so-called “fetishism”) are those one can pick up, grasp, and handle in the round. Müller claims that the Vedas are unconcerned with tangible objects. The significant point is to say that religion happens in the breakdown of perception, the incipient and emergent awareness of the Infinite as brought out in the struggle for language, and analytic ascriptions of agency and difference around those points at which perception reaches its limit, beginning to shimmer and lighten. Reading the Sanskrit sources, light is identified as the religious object or what we might call index par excellence.
As a social thinker, Müller is basically useless, although even as I say this somewhat off the cuff, I would be open to being proven wrong. To think of Müller in social terms would be to have to expand his theory to includes theorists for whom habits of perception, categories, and language itself are profoundly shared in and shaped by society. This would be an easy enough of a correction, for which one could turn already to Durkheim for help. What one can take from Müller, especially in relation to Marx, is a more sensual and more aesthetic form of “material religion,” more given to the formative powers of the imagination and language (concepts and naming).
Trying to assess the larger Müller corpus gets mixed up and screwy, and I’m not sure I’d recommend to anyone the four volumes of Gifford Lectures. These are [1] Natural Religion, [2] Physical Religion, [3] Anthropological Religion, [4] Theosophy or Psychological Religion. At least I would not recommend these to anyone whose interests does not lie in the history of the study of religion as simply antiquarian. There’s a musty quality to such theological speculation positioning Protestant Christianity at the apex in the history of religion, offered up to Christian readers as the most recondite meeting point or unity between “these two infinities” of God and soul.
Leaving aside the history of comparative religion that anchored his project, I would tease out the abiding theoretical interest in Müller’s orientation as a contribution to the study of the sense of religious phenomena in relation to ecology (nature), object theory (objects in nature), and affect theory (as to sensations that begin to break out at the sub-threshold of consciousness. Indeed, nature was the aspect of Müller’s work that caught Durkheim’s negative attention in his own attempt to uncover elementary, original forms of religious life.
For a theory of Judaism, one must always get past that automatic reflex to reduce material culture to “idolatry.” Reading Müller reminded me of all the tangible objects drawn from the Hebrew Bible that the great art critic Harold Rosenberg, tongue in cheek and inspired by surrealism, says that he would have wanted to place in a Museum of Jewish Art. (About Rosenberg I wrote here.) These would be more tangible, talismanic objects like Joseph’s coat, Balaam’s ass, the burning bush, Aaron’s rod, a slingshot, the jawbone of an ass, and other found-art objects and events that when chanced upon may, as per Rosenberg, “start to glisten with meaning and become memorable.”
http://ift.tt/2z85nah
0 notes
Photo
CHECK OUT OUR NEW SHORT FILM ! (see how below)
TITLE: Lamentation (Violet’s Song)
LENGTH: 60 seconds
DESCRIPTION: When Violet experiences a significant loss in her life, she discovers that grieving can be a long and lonely journey. She has to face some very hard questions and wait for answers that may never come.
EVERETT CONNECTOR FILMS: Ja Miller and Nathaniel Su met while studying art in Indiana. Since then they have written, scored, and produced a number of short films under the name Everett Connector Films. They view film as the ideal artistic medium for exploring how creating music and creating images can come together to tell a single story. Their highest recognition came in 2004, when their short "Lonesole" was selected to be screened at the Flickerings Film Festival in Illinois. "Lamentation (Violet’s Song)" marks the first film they’ve created in almost a decade.
This is a little film based on major themes from the Book of Lamentations and lament theology from the Book of Psalms. We basically tried to convey some theological ideas about engaging suffering and loss including: 1) waiting as a long and lonely journey that can be fundamental to maturing our trust; 2) grieving as an opportunity for us to express our fidelity/faithfulness to God; 3) asking what happens to our hope when God is absent or silent; and 4) exploring the tension/contradiction of biblical lament, which calls for a TRUST that is open-ended and open-handed and a COMPLAINT that is rooted in an underlying confidence. Hoping you can see the film and if you’re in the area vote for us!
DETAILS ABOUT SCREENINGS AND ONLINE VIEWING AND VOTING
WATCH THE FILM IN PERSON: Free film screenings will be available at The Nighlight Cinema on Saturday’s at 3:30 and 4:15, and Sunday’s at 6:45 and 7:30. Theater seating is limited. Voters are encouraged to reserve a FREE ticket to any of the available screenings at nightlightcinema.com.
WATCH THE FILM ONLINE: https://higharts.org/film/lamentation-violets-song/264/c9/
https://higharts.org/film/
MORE ABOUT THE FILM ITSELF
We were provoked to write a script when we found out about the High Arts Festival’s 60 Second Film Competition held here in downtown Akron, Ohio. We were fortunate enough to be able to work with a super talented actress from my church community named Kate Dwyer. She really brought Violet to life, and her performance captured the heart and vision of our screenplay. By the end of the film, Violet’s situation has not changed or moved much, but her small acts of confidence have left the door open for turning her suffering into something meaningful and honoring to God.
We designed and shot the film intentionally for black and white presentation. One of my all time biggest influences as a cinematographer is Alejandro González Iñárritu’s 21 Grams filmed by cinematographer Rodrigo Prieto. I was able to generally digitally reproduce the high speed Kodak 9289 film stock they intentionally shot with (giving the film it’s grainy gritty aesthetic) as well as render or “print” the final film in a way that reproduced both the film-type (Kodak Vision Premier 2393) and the “Bleach Bypass” process used on the final print of 21 Grams (in film, leaving the silver layer or bypassing bleaching the film causes high-contrast...especially between the deep shadows and glowing highlights).
One of the main elements in the film is an interplay between the main character Violet and a glass with violet flowers in it. The character was named Violet for at least 2 reasons: 1) violets symbolize faithfulness; and 2) Violet is the name of one of my favorite characters from television - a character for whom bravery is a fundamental quality.
Small bits of trivial information related to cinematography on our film - I love Tarantino Screenplays and Films. He’s also a major influence on my aesthetic as a film maker. One thing he does in most of his films is utilize a device called a “split diopter lens” (which actually has been used in tons of films, many of which you know). Basically, think of a camera lens with a “magnifying lens” over 1 half of it. When you use this lens it enables you to have sharp focus on both the subject in the background, but also in the foreground (all in one shot and while maintaining a shallow depth of field on the overall shot). One cool part of the aesthetic of this type of shot is the “blurry dividing line” you’ll see that is literally where the two halves of the lens are divided. We were able to find a vintage vivitar split diopter lens on ebay and it worked great for one of our final shots with Violet and the violets.
I was also able to find a vintage 8-element 28mm F2.8 Nikon prime lens that we used to shoot the entire film with. It’s a manual lens, so we pulled our own focus using the lens focus ring. I loved shooting that way and I think having to pull focus manually really affects the way you shoot and the way the film looks in the end. It was cool to feel the weight and texture of an old-timey metal lens again and to hear the loud mechanical clicks of the aperature. We tried to remain in mid-range apertures (F4-F8), to give it more of a “film” look.
Anyways hope you get a chance to watch our short.
0 notes
Photo
Aristotle
For other uses, see Aristotle (disambiguation). Aristotle (/ˈærɪˌstɒtəl/; Greek: Ἀριστοτέλης [aristotélɛːs], Aristotélēs; 384–322 BC) was a Greek philosopher and scientist born in the city of Stagira, Chalkidice, on the northern periphery of Classical Greece. His father, Nicomachus, died when Aristotle was a child, whereafter Proxenus of Atarneus became his guardian. At seventeen or eighteen, he joined Plato's Academy in Athens and remained there until the age of thirty-seven (c. 347 BC). His writings cover many subjects – including physics, biology, zoology, metaphysics, logic, ethics, aesthetics, poetry, theater, music, rhetoric, linguistics, politics and government – and constitute the first comprehensive system of Western philosophy. Shortly after Plato died, Aristotle left Athens and, at the request of Philip of Macedon, tutored Alexander the Great starting from 343 BC. Teaching Alexander the Great gave Aristotle many opportunities and an abundance of supplies. He established a library in the Lyceum which aided in the production of many of his hundreds of books. The fact that Aristotle was a pupil of Plato contributed to his former views of Platonism, but, following Plato's death, Aristotle immersed himself in empirical studies and shifted from Platonism to empiricism. He believed all peoples' concepts and all of their knowledge was ultimately based on perception. Aristotle's views on natural sciences represent the groundwork underlying many of his works. Aristotle's views on physical science profoundly shaped medieval scholarship. Their influence extended from Late Antiquity and the Early Middle Ages into the Renaissance, and were not replaced systematically until the Enlightenment and theories such as classical mechanics. Some of Aristotle's zoological observations, such as on the hectocotyl (reproductive) arm of the octopus, were not confirmed or refuted until the 19th century. His works contain the earliest known formal study of logic, which was incorporated in the late 19th century into modern formal logic. In metaphysics, Aristotelianism profoundly influenced Judeo-Islamic philosophical and theological thought during the Middle Ages and continues to influence Christian theology, especially the Neoplatonism of the Early Church and the scholastic tradition of the Roman Catholic Church. Aristotle was well known among medieval Muslim intellectuals and revered as "The First Teacher" (Arabic: المعلم الأول). His ethics, though always influential, gained renewed interest with the modern advent of virtue ethics. All aspects of Aristotle's philosophy continue to be the object of active academic study today. Though Aristotle wrote many elegant treatises and dialogues – Cicero described his literary style as "a river of gold" – it is thought that only around a third of his original output has survived. More details Android, Windows
1 note
·
View note
Text
Hyperallergic: On a Foggy Film Set, Karl Marx Sings “The Internationale”
Installation view of Quid Pro Quo by Willy Kautz (all images courtesy of the artist and El Cuarto de Maquinas; photo by Víctor Mendoza)
MEXICO CITY — The ambiguous confluence of religion, capitalism, and communism creates a playful thematic triangle in Willy Kautz’s new exhibition at El Cuarto de Maquinas, Quid Pro Quo. Despite the weight of the subject matter, the work bears the lightness of a film set, creating theatrical contradictions where Karl Marx plays the role of instigator and protagonist within a décor painted communist red, gilded with gold leaf like a religious shrine, and lit up with neon like a nightclub. With this exhibition Kautz, a prolific Mexican curator, is using his ongoing Jippies Asquerosos (or “dirty hippies”) project to investigate the nature of making and curating art in the 21st century, when the boundary between creators and organizers is being steadily chipped away by the chisels of digitalism.
At irregular intervals, since 2005, Kautz has staged Jippies Asquerosos in different iterations and within different spaces, always with a common thread of arguably serious subject mater, often juxtaposed with lighthearted or even comic references to cinema and nightlife — especially trance music. Despite long pauses between projects, two elements recur in each new iteration of Kautz’s experiment in curation: the same red neon sign spelling out Jippies Asquerosos and a fog machine, which, in the present instance, tweak the tone of the show toward the mystical and playful. The project as a whole is overtly theatrical, suggesting that art — as much as the show’s thematic triumvirate of communism, religion, and capitalism — is full of pageantry.
Willy Kautz, “Quid Pro Quo I (Objeto endemoniado)” (2016), gold leaf on wood, 100 x 100 cm
Here, El Cuarto de Maquinas’ shiny new gallery space is divided into three sections, reflecting the three aforementioned themes. The first gallery, the most formal, is adorned with a series of seven golden wood blocks hung like paintings and titled “Quid Pro Quo I,” “Quid Pro Quo II,” etc. The main gallery space leads into “Ver la Madera por el Árbol” (or “To See the Wood for the Tree”), an installation in which Christmas trees, fog, and neon light blend into each other, creating an atmosphere akin to that of a twisted nightclub. Finally, an animation featuring the image of Marx, “Cinemarx,” rounds out Kautz’s convoluted amalgamation.
Installation view of Quid Pro Quo by Willy Kautz
The aesthetic of the exhibition suggests the showiness of a catholic cathedral, albeit one flanked by walls painted bright red. Quotations from Marx’s critique of capitalism take the place of religious texts in the series of wood blocks covered in gold leaf and carved with key passages like: “A commodity appears, at first sight, a very trivial thing, and easily understood. Its analysis shows that it is, in reality, a very queer thing, abounding in metaphysical subtleties and theological niceties.” The show includes similarly self-referential punch lines hidden in every piece; its title, Quid Pro Quo, was also taken from Marx’s theory of use and exchange value, but, ironically, today the Latin phrase is used in creative industries as code for free labor.
Installation view of Quid Pro Quo by Willy Kautz
The conglomeration of forms Kautz has arranged in the T-shaped gallery alludes to the commodity fetishism that rots religion, politics, industry, and art. Communism, a system intended to achieve optimal equality, becomes atrophied by self-professed demigods (Vladimir Lenin, Fidel Castro, Kim Jong-un, or Marx himself); religion, a promised means toward immaterial fulfillment, gets bogged down in pageantry and material riches. Kautz blends all this together into a maze of contradictions and clever nods at adulteration. He highlights the Sisyphean nature of our quests for immaculate knowledge, ridiculing the promise of endless progress.
Willy Kautz, “Jippies Asquerosos” (2016), neon, dimensions variable
In the animation, Marx is likened to the jolly, white-bearded Santa Claus, whose modern image, as Kautz pointed out to Hyperallergic during a walk through the show, was developed by Coca-Cola. The analogy between Marx and Coke’s quintessential, capitalist Santa is implied without any direct comparison. Nearby, red ornaments adorn a small grove of Christmas trees from which the fog machine ominously puffs clouds of dissipating smoke that the adjacent neon light catches, coloring the air red and leaving behind the specific stench of fog fluid, like the residual potential energy from a party. Finally, as the fog from within the browning Christmas trees dissolves into the red light of the neon “Jippies Asquerosos” sign, the last wisps of artificial mist are pierced by a projector beam casting Marx’s animated image on a wall painted gold.
The animation is the final iteration of a collage from which Kautz extrapolated the entire show. It shows Marx on stage in an empty auditorium, belting out “The Internationale” anthem to a non-existent audience. The beam from the projector cuts through the residual fog like lasers in a nightclub. The projection becomes sculptural and the anthem becomes a sort of trance, repeating over and over again. Since its composition in the middle of the 19th century, “The Internationale” has been adopted by socialist, anarchist, and communist movements, and was later chosen as the official national anthem of the Soviet Union. Here, however, the optimistic hymn falls on deaf ears, bouncing off crimson walls and gilded surfaces.
Willy Kautz, “Quid Pro Quo (El secreto)” (2016), gold leaf on wood, 100 x 100 cm
Willy Kautz, “Ver la madera por el árbol” (2016), pine trees, fog machine, and light, dimensions variable
Willy Kautz, “Ver la madera por el árbol” (2016), pine trees, fog machine, and light, dimensions variable
Quid Pro Quo by Willy Kautz is on view at El Cuarto de Maquinas (Colima 159, Roma Norte, Mexico City) through March 11.
The post On a Foggy Film Set, Karl Marx Sings “The Internationale” appeared first on Hyperallergic.
from Hyperallergic http://ift.tt/2lNPkVN via IFTTT
0 notes