#No Context Crow No. 281
Explore tagged Tumblr posts
Text

No Context Crow #281: Locket Crow
If this image is yours or you know who created it, let me know!
#crows#corvids#corvidae#birds#animals#art#drawing#illustration#locket#heart locket#necklace#jewelry#painting#watercolor#multimedia#(? or so I think)#daily crows#crow queue#No Context Crow No. 281
62 notes
·
View notes
Text
Thought Provoking Books & Books That Have Important Voices! Pt. 29
281. Beloved by Toni Morrison (Historical Fiction/Magical Realism/Slavery/Memory/Trauma/Motherhood/Ghost Story/Challenged Book)
282. Immodest Acts: The Life of a Lesbian Nun in Renaissance Italy by Judith C. Brown (Gender Studies/Religious History/Sexuality & Religion/Women's Power & Agency/Social & Cultural Context/Historical Investigation)
283. Diana: In Pursuit of Love by Andrew Morton (Challenged Book/Nonfiction/Biography/Memoir)
284. The Warrior Queens by Antonia Fraser (Nonfiction/History/Biography/Feminism/European History/War/Medieval)
285. Fool's Crow by James Welch (Banned Book/Historical Fiction/Cultural Loss/Colonialism/Spirituality/Connection to the Natural World/Coming of Age/Impact of Westward Expansion on Native American Tribes/Blackfeet Nation/Individual v Community)
286. When the Stars Go Dark by Paula McLain (Suspense/Psychological Thriller/Crime Fiction/Trauma)
287. Go the F* to Sleep by Adam Mansbach (Bedtime Book for Parents/Challenged Book/Humor)
288. The Bog Wife by Kay Chronister (Appalachian/Folk/Gothic/Horror/Fantasy/Magical Realism/Adult)
289. How to Be a Woman by Caitlin Moran (Challenged Book/Nonfiction Memoir/British Writer/Views on Feminism/Humor)
290. Devotions: The Selected Poems of Mary Oliver by Mary Oliver (Poems/Nature/Spirituality/The Human Experience/Queer/Adult)
#the random things#books#books and libraries#books to read#bookworm#freedom#freedom to read#important#books and reading#important writings#book dragon#book discussion#bookstore#booklr#banned books#book lovers#book recommendations#book recs#book tumblr#bookblr#books and literature#booksbooksbooks#bookshelf#bookstagram#booktok#reading challenge#bookish#book blog#feed your soul#feed your head
5 notes
·
View notes
Text
I posted 2,908 times in 2021
770 posts created (26%)
2138 posts reblogged (74%)
For every post I created, I reblogged 2.8 posts.
I added 2,019 tags in 2021
#fictif last legacy - 421 posts
#fictif - 396 posts
#the arcana - 365 posts
#last legacy - 156 posts
#crow asks - 151 posts
#fictif felix - 137 posts
#fictif sage - 120 posts
#fictif anisa - 111 posts
#the arcana game - 99 posts
#crow rambles - 63 posts
Longest Tag: 133 characters
#fun fact my art history professor said when she went to the pantheon when she was in college there was a mcdonald’s across the street
My Top Posts in 2021
#5
My Partner Reacts to Arcana Characters with a Little Context
A few of you asked and you shall receive 😌
I’ve talked about Arcana quite a bit with my partner so they know lil bits here and there
We’ll start with the main 6

See the full post
255 notes • Posted 2021-04-11 03:36:40 GMT
#4

When your whole family is emo but you
281 notes • Posted 2021-04-23 17:51:06 GMT
#3


See the full post
295 notes • Posted 2021-02-15 02:54:29 GMT
#2
Analysis of Vesuvia :) Pt 1
No one asked for this yet here I am
Part 2, Part 3A, Part 3B,
This all started cause of @helpiminhell ‘s post
I started thinking about this last year while playing Julian’s route. At the very beginning it has a scene where the Apprentice finds Julian and says he’s “standing at the aqueduct” which confused me because Aqueducts traditionally look like this

This is a Roman aqueduct, more specifically the Pont du Gard, in France. Now I’m not saying that the only the Romans had aqueducts, there are ones that exist in other parts of the world, I am just more familiar with this one. And it resembles the Vesuvian aqueducts.
Aqueducts are built at a slight angle so that mountain water can be transported to cities to provide fresh water. So they’re VERY tall and VERY high up.
Ok first of all lets start by looking at Vesuvia itself
See the full post
398 notes • Posted 2021-03-19 20:41:51 GMT
#1
See the full post
412 notes • Posted 2021-03-01 02:36:47 GMT
Get your Tumblr 2021 Year in Review →
#Bro Im so glad my art history post made it on here that series took days off my lifespan lmaaoo#been back on tumblr for nearly a year now#love yall <3
2 notes
·
View notes
Text
@ocean-settler in regards to ‘jamie is azor ahai’
there are a few necessary things for someone to be a candidate for the prince who was promised/azor ahai:
be born under a bleeding red star
be born of salt
be born of smoke
live whilst “the darkness gathers”
have the “blood of the dragon”/descended from aerys and rhaella targaryen
wake dragons from stone
wield lightbringer
have links to ‘the song of ice and fire’
most of these can be pretty nicely applied to jaime, i think
being born under a bleeding red star
there are four possible events that could count as “when the red star bleeds”: the comet that was seen during the year of aegon targaryen’s birth; the red messenger comet that appears during the events we see taking place; oberyn martell’s death; or elia martell’s death.
the comets are the things everyone cites as fitting this part of the prophecy – they’re literal red stars that are described as looking like they’re bleeding – but oberyn and elia’s deaths slip under the radar as possibilities. but thinking about it, what is the banner of house martell? a red sun – a red star. so “when the red star bleeds” could refer to the death of a martell. two major martells die at important junctures during the story, oberyn and elia. either of them could be the red star.
so what was jaime doing during these events? was he being reborn? well, yes.
the year of first red star, aegon’s comet, was either 281 AC. jaime was raised to knighthood and joined the kingsguard in 281, a kind of birth as he becomes a new person and dedicates himself to a cause. interestingly, 281 was the year of the false spring – it’s certainly notable that jaime’s ‘birth’ into knighthood happened in a year with not only a bleeding star, but also what appeared to be a winter’s end.
the second red star’s bleeding is elia martell’s death, which, admittedly, jaime had little to do with directly. however, he was in the red keep, murdering aerys, at the same time as clegane was murdering elia. in other words, jaime was reborn as the kingslayer in the same building, at the same time as a red star bled.
the year of the second comet, the red messenger, signals the beginning of jaime’s character development. his journey during a storm of swords and the relationship between him and brienne changes him from someone with a relatively poor code of honour (his association with cersei’s schemeing and his pushing a kid out of a window are two examples) into a more honourable man (saving brienne from rape and from the bear pit despite it being in his best interest not to).
the last bleeding red star is oberyn’s death. jaime, although his name is never mentioned during tyrion’s trial by combat, was not only almost certainly present, but in the aftermath of the trial and oberyn’s death had a significant change of heart, siding with tyrion instead of his sister and beginning along the path away from loving her. their relationship, at least in the books, essentially fizzles and dies at this point, marking a new page in jaime’s life.
any or all of these events could be the bleeding red star the prophecy refers to – it’s extraordinarily notable that jaime was actively changing during all of them.
born of salt and smoke
there are two ways the “births” in the azor ahai prophecy can be interpreted: the birth of salt and smoke is a single event, or the birth of salt and the birth of smoke are two different events. either way, i think they could be applied to jaime.
if they are the same event, then one answer is his de-handing by vargo hoate (and zollo). here’s the full passage:
Still, still, long after they had snuffed out the torch they’d used to sear his bloody stump, days after, he could still feel the fire lancing up his arm, and his fingers twisting in the flames, the fingers he no longer had.
He had taken wounds before, but never like this. He had never known there could be such pain. Sometimes, unbidden, old prayers bubbled from his lips, prayers he learned as a child and never thought of since, prayers he had first prayed with Cersei kneeling beside him in the sept at Casterly Rock. Sometimes he even wept, until he heard the Mummers laughing. Then he made his eyes go dry and his heart go dead, and prayed for his fever to burn away his tears. Now I know how Tyrion has felt, all those times they laughed at him.
the smoke being that from the fire used to cauterised his wound, the salt being his tears due to the pain. in many ways, it’s similar to rhaegar’s idea that the “salt and smoke” was summerhall, in that the smoke was from the flames and the salt was from people weeping for the tragedy.
the other possibility is in his last chapter of a feast for crows. in this chapter, jaime dreams of his mother, a vision essentially telling him to abandon the lannister dreams of glory and success. in the dream, his mother cries, and he wakes up to a letter from his sister asking him to come to fight in her trial by combat – a letter which he burns. tears = salt, burning paper = smoke, and jaime is reborn as he forsakes his sister completely.
while subtle, both of these possibilities work well, though it must be acknowledged that it’s also entirely possible that jaime’s birth of salt and smoke is an event which happened yet, and may in the future be a much more significant revelation of his status as azor ahai.
live whilst “the darkness gathers”
this is perhaps the most obvious one, being the beginning of winter and the rise of the Others, and is not jaime specific since it can be applied to any azor ahai candidate
have the “blood of the dragon”/descended from aerys and rhaella targaryen
this one is... trickier.
there’s a relatively popular theory going around that tyrion is not actually a lannister, but instead the child of aerys targaryen and joanna lannister. it’s stated in-text that aerys was sexually interested in joanna, so it’s not outside of the realm of possibility that she sired his child.
or children.
because there’s no reason to discard that idea that it might not be tyrion that’s aerys’ bastard, but jaime and cersei instead. in fact, it would be a pretty satisfying poetic justice if tyrion was tywin’s only trueborn son, instead of the twins he was so proud of.
it’s textually stated that jaime and cersei are unlike tywin. cersei thinks she has inherited tywin’s intelligence and ability to scheme, but with every turn she proves herself incompetent. likewise, jaime is told by his aunt that
"You smile like Gerion and fight like Tyg, and there's some of Kevan in you, else you would not wear that cloak... but Tyrion is Tywin's son, not you."
it appears in a metaphorical context, but what if this is not only metaphor, but foreshadowing as well. if jaime and cersei are in fact aerys’ children, then they truly have the blood of the dragon.
the problematic element here appears to be that they don’t have rhaella targaryen’s blood. barristan selmy tells daenerys that the ghost of high heart apparently prophesised azor ahai would be born of aerys and rhaella. however, when examining the actual quote, that’s not necessarily true:
“Your grandsire commanded it. A woods witch had told him that the prince was promised would be born of their line.”
not born of them, born of their line. the targaryens were so inbred that they had no new genetic material entering their line – marrying brother to sister kept the bloodline ‘pure’. aerys and rhaella, through centuries of inbreeding, were essentially genetic copies of each other – any child of aerys’ would essentially be of rhaella’s line too. therefore, it doesn’t matter that jaime is aerys’ child and not rhaella’s. he is still the child of their bloodline, and thus an azor ahai candidate.
however, if this theory turns out not to be true, then jaime is still not necessarily discredited. “born of their line” sounds almost too straightforward to be a direct quote from a prophecy. i would kill for the exact wording of the woods witch’s prophecy, but i reckon it would more likely have been worded something like, “the prince who was promised will have the blood of rhaella and aerys”. and even if jaime is not aerys’ son, he still has aerys and rhaella’s blood.
he has their blood on his hands. he directly killed aerys, literally soaking him in targaryen blood, and also stood by and did nothing whilst knowing that elia was being raped and murdered on the other side of the castle. jaime has their bloodline on his hands no matter his parentage
wake dragons from stone
this part of the prophecy is linked to the blood of the dragon. if cersei and jaime discover their true heritage, it will be the metaphorical ‘awakening’ of two dragons – two new targaryens. and the stone they wake from? casterly rock. the dragons born on the rock will wake up. as simple as that.
if the twins are not secret targaryens, this becomes more difficult. several theories:
the dragonstone volcano erupts (highly unlikely but AWESOME)
skaagos volcano erupts (see above)
aegon gets greyscale and is cured (boring)
the dragon carvings on dragonstone come to life (ALSO AWESOME)
the petrified dragons on dragonstone get cured of greyscale (AMAZING)
there are dragons on skaagos (too obscure, maybe?)
sansa/alayne stone marries aegon and has a kid (highly questionable but i kinda like this one)
someone slow to anger gets pissed off (think viserys’ “waking the dragon” threats) (kinda hilarious)
eh i don’t know. i just feel like dany’s dragon’s and jon’s lineage are too obvious answers
wield lightbringer
lightbringer, “the red sword of heroes”, appears to have been recreated during the books by several characters – stannis, beric dondarrion, perhaps even daenerys (some suggest that her lightbringers are her dragons). some theorise that the actual historical lightbringer survived through the ages as ice (the stark sword), or dawn (the sword of house dayne).
i’d like to suggest another potential sword to become lightbringer: oathkeeper
in a storm of swords, jaime sleeps against the stump of a weirwood tree and has a dream about a burning sword. here’s the full text:
“Give me a sword, at least.”
“I gave you a sword,” Lord Tywin said.
It was at his feet. Jaime groped under the water until his hand closed upon the hilt. Nothing can hurt me so long as I have a sword. As he raised the sword a finger of pale flame flickered at the point and crept up along the edge, stopping a hand’s breath from the hilt. The fire took on the color of the steel itself so it burned with a silvery-blue light, and the gloom pulled back.
From behind came a great splash. Jaime whirled toward the sound . . . but the faint light revealed only Brienne of Tarth, her hands bound in heavy chains. “I swore to keep you safe,” the wench said stubbornly. “I swore an oath.” Naked, she raised her hands to Jaime. “Ser. Please. If you would be so good.”
The steel links parted like silk. “A sword,” Brienne begged, and there it was, scabbard, belt, and all. She buckled it around her thick waist. The light was so dim that Jaime could scarcely see her, though they stood a scant few feet apart. In this light she could almost be a beauty, he thought. In this light she could almost be a knight. Brienne’s sword took flame as well, burning silvery blue. The darkness retreated a little more.
this dream sword is oathkeeper:
tywin says “i gave you a sword”, referring to oathkeeper, which jaime is given by tywin later on (that this is a weirwood dream makes it understandable that jaime has knowledge from the future)
“i swore an oath” directly parallels the sword’s name, oathkeeper
dream-brienne gains a sword with the same characteristics as jaime’s dream-sword. the only sword jaime and brienne share is oathkeeper
the evidence against this sword being oathkeeper is that the blade is silver-blue, not grey-red, but then again visions have never been the most reliable when pertaining to azor ahai (or how else could melisandre have been so mistaken about stannis?). the only other explanation i can think of for this is that it’s symbolic, representing jaime becoming more like brienne, the ‘blue knight’ of renly’s rainbow guard.
regardless of whether or not the sword is oathkeeper, it cannot be ignored that the swords in jaime’s dream have burning blades, something specified in the azor ahai prophecies.
furthermore, we know two things for certain about oathkeeper: it is valyrian steel, and it is red.
that it is valyrian steel matters here – whilst it has not yet been confirmed in the books, the tv show has revealed that valyrian steel is one of the few materials which can kill white walkers. i would be extraordinarily surprised if this doesn’t turn out to be true in the books as well.
lastly, as tyrion notes in a storm of swords:
Most Valyrian steel was a grey so dark it looked almost black, as was true here as well. But blended into the folds was a red so deep as the grey.
“red sword of heroes”, anyone?
have links to the song of ice and fire
here’s a nice quote from grrm himself:
I mean... Fire is love, fire is passion, fire is sexual ardor and all of these things. Ice is betrayal, ice is revenge, ice is… you know, that kind of cold inhumanity and all that stuff is being played out in the books.
if this doesn’t describe jaime better than any other character in the series, i don’t know what more i can do to convince you
0 notes
Text
Ramos v. Louisiana and the Jim Crow Origins of Nonunanimous Juries
Ramos v. Louisiana, decided by the U.S. Supreme Court last Monday and summarized here, holds that the Sixth Amendment impartial jury guarantee gives defendants a right to a unanimous jury verdict in state trials. The case is making waves for reasons tangential to the dispute between the parties: in a dizzyingly split opinion, the justices argue more over the meaning of stare decisis (the court’s obligation to follow its prior holdings) than whether defendants in state courts may be convicted by a less-than-unanimous jury. This aspect of the opinion has been widely discussed (see analysis here, here, here, and here), and foreshadows the justices’ likely battle over an upcoming reproductive rights case. Since the divergent perspectives on stare decisis have been covered elsewhere, I will consider another issue that split the justices: the legal relevance of the nonunanimous jury law’s Jim Crow origins.
First, a pop quiz
Did North Carolina ever allow non unanimous jury verdicts in criminal trials? Read on for the answer.
The facts and procedural history of the case
Evangelisto Ramos was charged with a second-degree murder in New Orleans in 2014. He maintained his innocence and invoked his right to a jury trial. At the conclusion of the trial, ten jurors found Mr. Ramos guilty and two jurors found him not guilty. In the 48 states (including North Carolina) and federal court where all jurors must agree on a guilty verdict to convict a defendant, this would have resulted in a hung jury and a mistrial. Instead, because he was tried in Louisiana (before voters repealed the nonunanimous jury provision in 2019), Mr. Ramos was convicted and sentenced to life in prison without the possibility of parole. Appellate courts in Louisiana affirmed the conviction, relying on Apodaca v. Oregon, 406 U.S. 404 (1972), which had declined to extend the Sixth Amendment right to a unanimous jury to the states under the Fourteenth Amendment. The Supreme Court granted certiorari and reversed Mr. Ramos’s conviction.
Mr. Ramos’s Sixth Amendment challenge
Mr. Ramos asserted that the nonunanimous jury verdict violated his Sixth Amendment right to a unanimous jury. His argument rested on the historical and continued meaning of the Sixth Amendment right to a trial by an impartial jury, which provides that “[i]n all criminal prosecutions, the accused shall enjoy the right to a speedy and public trial, by an impartial jury[.]” He argued that the impartial jury guarantee, at the time the Sixth Amendment was adopted in 1789, included the right to a unanimous jury verdict. Neither party disputed that the right to a unanimous jury verdict was central to the jury trial right at common law, dating back to 1367. See Douglas G. Smith, The Historical and Constitutional Contexts of Jury Reform, 25 Hofstra L. Rev. 377, 397 (1996). The U.S. Supreme Court has referenced that history on several occasions, at one point describing the common law right to a unanimous jury as so widely known that “[n]o authorities are needed to sustain this proposition.” Am. Publ’g Co. v. Fisher, 166 U.S. 464, 468 (1897). And the Supreme Court had already agreed that the purpose and effect of the impartial jury guarantee of the Sixth Amendment was to codify the common law meaning of the jury right, including the right to a unanimous verdict. See, e.g., Patton v. United States, 281 U. S. 276, 288 (1930). The only question before the Ramos court was the applicability of that aspect of the right to the states—whether the right was incorporated under the Fourteenth Amendment to bind states as well as the federal government. The biggest hurdle for Mr. Ramos to overcome was that the earlier decision, Apodaca, already answered this question in the negative.
Nonunanimous jury verdicts sound race-neutral: what’s race got to do with it?
Justice Gorsuch begins his opinion, in a portion joined by a narrow majority of the justices (Justices Breyer, Ginsburg, Sotomayor, and Kavanaugh), with a history lesson not on the Sixth Amendment but on nonunanimous juries in Louisiana. It is an ugly history, revealing a white supremacist backlash to the growing rights and political power of black people at the end of the nineteenth century. The move away from unanimous juries in Louisiana emerged in response to constitutional, statutory, and judicial efforts to secure the rights of black people to serve on juries through the adoption of the Fourteenth Amendment in 1868, the Civil Rights Act of 1875, and the U.S. Supreme Court’s decision in Strauder v. West Virginia, 100 U.S. 303 (1880) (holding that racial discrimination in jury selection compromises the right of trial by jury and violates the Equal Protection Clause). Justice Gorsuch explains that the nonunanimous jury provision originated in Louisiana’s 1898 constitutional convention, the purpose of which, according to one committee chairman, was to “establish the supremacy of the white race.” Ramos v. Louisiana, Slip. Op. at 2. Alongside other Jim Crow provisions intended to disenfranchise black people, including a poll tax and combined literacy and property ownership test, the nonunanimous jury provision targeted black people without explicitly naming this intent in its text. “With a careful eye on racial demographics, the convention delegates sculpted a facially race-neutral rule permitting 10-to-2 verdicts in order to ensure that African-American juror service would be meaningless.” Slip Op. at 2 (internal quotations omitted).
Justice Kavanaugh explains why nonunanimous jury provisions limit the influence of black jurors on the outcome of criminal trials:
Then and now, non-unanimous juries can silence the voices and negate the votes of black jurors, especially in cases with black defendants or black victims, and only one or two black jurors. The 10 jurors “can simply ignore the views of their fellow panel members of a different race or class.” Johnson v. Louisiana, 406 U. S. 356, 397 (1972) (Stewart, J., dissenting). That reality—and the resulting perception of unfairness and racial bias—can undermine confidence in and respect for the criminal justice system. The non-unanimous jury operates much the same as the unfettered peremptory challenge, a practice that for many decades likewise functioned as an engine of discrimination against black defendants, victims, and jurors. In effect, the non-unanimous jury allows backdoor and unreviewable peremptory strikes against up to 2 of the 12 jurors.
Slip Op. at 35 (Kavanaugh, J., concurring in part).
In 1974, Louisiana readopted its nonunanimous jury provision. Why? The justices don’t seem sure. Justice Gorsuch briefly concludes that “it’s hard to say why these laws persist”; Justice Kavanaugh speculates that the continued reliance on nonunanimous juries “may have been motivated by neutral principles (or just by inertia)”; and Justice Alito notes that the stated purpose of the nonunanimous jury provision in 1974 was judicial efficiency and, in the debate, “no mention was made of race.” Slip Op. at 3 (Alito, J., dissenting). But Justice Sotomayor observes that when it comes to old laws originally motivated by racial animus, it is often the case that “States’ legislatures never truly grapple[] with the laws’ sordid history in reenacting them.” Slip Op. at 33 (Sotomayor, J., concurring in part). She finds that Louisiana’s only effort to do so came not in 1974 but just last year, when Louisiana voters approved a 2019 referendum repealing the nonunanimous jury provision. The campaign for a unanimous jury right focused in part on the racist origins and continuing racially disparate outcomes of the nonunanimous jury law.
Raise your hand if you think that the Jim Crow origins of Louisiana’s nonunanimous jury provision is important to consider in this case
Not all nine justices think we should consider this history. Only five do. Four justices share Justice Gorsuch’s perspective that the racist history of Louisiana’s nonunanimous jury verdict law matters here. Concurring in most of Justice Gorsuch’s opinion, Justice Sotomayor writes separately to stress how important the Jim Crow history is to the invalidity of nonunanimous juries. Justice Kavanaugh also spends part of his lengthy concurrence discussing the significance of the racism that gave rise to nonunanimous juries. Justice Thomas ignores the Jim Crow history altogether, and Justice Alito, joined by Justice Kagan and Chief Justice Roberts, seems more offended by the majority’s audacity to observe that racism underpinned the nonunanimous jury provision than by the racism itself. Slip Op. at 62-66 (Alito, J., dissenting).
It may sound unremarkable that five justices in this case examine the racist history underlying Louisiana’s nonunanimous jury provision. In reviewing the constitutionality of a provision arising out of a white supremacist state constitutional convention, wouldn’t the Court have to reckon with that history? Certainly, if Mr. Ramos had raised an equal protection challenge to his nonunanimous jury verdict, the Court would have been squarely presented with the legal question of whether the nonunanimous jury provision was unlawful because it was motivated by a discriminatory purpose and had a discriminatory effect. But outside the equal protection context, the U.S. Supreme Court has marginalized the relevance of racist intent when such a consideration is not an essential element of a defendant’s legal claim, for example, when a traffic stop is challenged as racially motivated in violation of the Fourth Amendment. See, e.g., Whren v. United States, 517 U.S. 806, 813 (1996) (“[T]he Constitution prohibits selective enforcement of the law based on considerations such as race. But the constitutional basis for objecting to intentionally discriminatory application of laws is the Equal Protection Clause, not the Fourth Amendment. Subjective intentions play no role in ordinary, probable-cause Fourth Amendment analysis.”).
Why did a majority of the Court look so closely at this history in Ramos, and what exactly did they do with it? It is easy enough to note that five justices think that the racist origins of the law matter here and four justices apparently think they don’t. The more difficult question is how and why that history matters. How, if at all, does Jim Crow history influence the justices’ resolution of the legal questions before them in Ramos?
The answer is elusive. Justice Gorsuch highlights the racist origins of the law and criticizes the Apodaca plurality for ignoring that history, but in a footnote concedes that his discussion of Louisiana’s white supremacist constitutional convention is dicta, as nonunanimous juries would violate the Sixth Amendment impartial jury guarantee whether or not they were designed to diminish the influence of black jurors. Justice Sotomayor emphasizes that “the racially biased origins of the Louisiana and Oregon laws uniquely matter here,” but what does it mean legally to “matter”? Does the history matter because it serves as important context; because the Court has an ethical obligation to acknowledge painful aspects of our history (a “never again” perspective); or does it somehow factor into the resolution of the questions before the Court? She does not detail how the Jim Crow origins of Louisiana’s nonunanimous juries affect the Court’s analysis of the legal issues. She implies that an equal protection claim may have succeeded here, referencing the analogous case of United States v. Fordice, 505 U. S. 717, 729 (1992), which held that policies “‘traceable’ to a State’s de jure racial segregation and that still ‘have discriminatory effects’ offend the Equal Protection Clause.”
Justice Kavanaugh alone specifies how the origins of Louisiana’s nonunanimous juries influence the resolution of this case. He concludes that, once the court has determined that the correct resolution of the issues conflicts with a prior court holding (here, the Apodaca ruling), the court is more justified in departing from precedent when it has caused “significant negative jurisprudential or real-world consequences.” Slip Op. at 42 (Kavanaugh, J., concurring in part). The nonunanimous jury provision “tolerates and reinforces a practice that is thoroughly racist in its origins and has continuing racially discriminatory effects,” a significant negative consequence. This framework brings the Jim Crow history into the stare decisis analysis, not the determination of the scope of the Sixth Amendment right to a unanimous jury, or whether, under the Fourteenth Amendment, this right binds the states.
Why does the Jim Crow discussion feature so prominently? Is it easier for justices to confront vestiges of racism (a la Ramos) than to confront contemporary allegations of more widespread racial bias (a la Whren)? Or perhaps the justices are more likely to consider racism as relevant when ruling on Sixth Amendment challenges involving the right to a jury trial? Recently, in Pena-Rodriguez v. Colorado, 137 S. Ct. 855, 867 (2017), the U.S. Supreme Court held that in cases involving evidence of racial bias in juror deliberations, the rule preventing the court from hearing juror testimony about statements made during deliberations must yield so that the court may consider whether the alleged racial bias violated the defendant’s Sixth Amendment right to a fair trial. That was not an equal protection case, but a case concerning the right to a fair and impartial jury, and the Court’s decision rested (as Justice Kavanaugh explains in Ramos) on a recognition of “the imperative to purge racial prejudice from the administration of justice generally and from the jury system in particular.” Id. at 13–14 (quoting Pena-Rodriguez and collecting cases). So, a working theory: when a defendant asserts a Fourth Amendment right, racial bias generally doesn’t matter, but when asserting a Sixth Amendment right, it might? Or maybe, as my colleague Shea Denning has considered and Justice Ginsburg has suggested, Whren was wrongly decided?
The bottom line here is that a majority of the court concluded that it is important to consider Jim Crow history when ruling on whether the unanimous verdict aspect of the Sixth Amendment right to a jury trial applies to the states. Although the justices in the majority do not agree on how this history factors into the analysis, the decision suggests that Jim Crow origins may support the invalidation of laws even outside of equal protection challenges.
What does this mean in states like North Carolina where jury unanimity was already guaranteed?
The holding in Ramos does not have immediate implications for North Carolina, where people accused of crimes already had a right to a unanimous jury. However, it raises interesting questions about the possibility that Jim Crow laws may have evolved into current law without careful examination or reconsideration. Kavanaugh asserts that the “nonunanimous jury is today the last of Louisiana’s Jim Crow laws.” (Slip. Op. Kavanaugh, J., concurring, at 48.) Assuming that this is true, what about in other states? What about here?
In 1898, the year of Louisiana’s constitutional convention, North Carolina saw similar white supremacist political activity, propaganda, and related violence, including the only successful political coup in United States history, in which white supremacists overthrew the city government of Wilmington, killing numerous black residents, forcing the resignation of the mayor, police chief, and aldermen, and burning down the headquarters of a black newspaper. Caleb Crain, City Limits: What a white-supremacist coup looks like, The New Yorker, April 27, 2020. As in Louisiana, “white supremacists went on to alter state law so as to disenfranchise black people[;]” while there were “more than a hundred and twenty-five thousand registered black voters in North Carolina in 1896 . . . only six thousand or so were still on the books by 1902.” Id. at 67. See also Thomas W. Frampton, The Jim Crow Jury, 71 Vanderbilt Law Review 1593, 1613-14 fns 118, 123, 124 (2019) (quoting articles published in 1898 and 1899 in the Semi-Weekly Messenger, a Wilmington newspaper, making white supremacist appeals for nonunanimous juries, one of which suggests that nonunanimous jury verdicts will reduce the need for lynchings). Are any of the laws passed in this era and motivated by this campaign of white supremacy still on the books?
The answer, almost certainly, is yes. Consider the North Carolina law making it a felony to vote when ineligible, even if the voter is unaware that he or she is ineligible to vote. This law dates back nearly unaltered to this same political effort to disenfranchise black voters around the turn of the twentieth century. Are there others? Some aspects of jury selection, including the use of peremptory strikes, have been historically entangled with discrimination. See April Anderson, Peremptory Challenges at the Turn of the Nineteenth Century: Development of Modern Jury Selection Strategies as Seen in Practitioners’ Trial Manuals 16 Stan. J. C.R. & C.L. 1 (2020). Historians at UNC are working on documenting North Carolina’s Jim Crow Laws, which may help identify others still in operation.
Justice Sotomayor’s concurrence in Ramos cautions that we may be governed by dated laws, in North Carolina and elsewhere, that have been reenacted or maintained without meaningful consideration of their Jim Crow origins and purpose. At least some of our legal architecture is built on the same troubling historical foundations described in Ramos. The splintered Ramos opinion does not provide a roadmap for resolving legal challenges related to Jim Crow laws—outside the usual equal protection approach—but a majority of the justices insist that this history cannot be ignored.
About that pop quiz
Yes, North Carolina briefly allowed non-unanimous jury verdicts in the 17th century. See Williams v. Florida, 399 U.S. 78, 98 n.45 (1970). I don’t know what motivated the adoption of nonunanimous juries in North Carolina or the return to unanimity. If you know more about this history, please leave a comment, and of course, feel free to comment on any other issues raised by the Ramos decision.
The post Ramos v. Louisiana and the Jim Crow Origins of Nonunanimous Juries appeared first on North Carolina Criminal Law.
Ramos v. Louisiana and the Jim Crow Origins of Nonunanimous Juries published first on https://immigrationlawyerto.tumblr.com/
0 notes
Text
Ramos v. Louisiana and the Jim Crow Origins of Nonunanimous Juries
Ramos v. Louisiana, decided by the U.S. Supreme Court last Monday and summarized here, holds that the Sixth Amendment impartial jury guarantee gives defendants a right to a unanimous jury verdict in state trials. The case is making waves for reasons tangential to the dispute between the parties: in a dizzyingly split opinion, the justices argue more over the meaning of stare decisis (the court’s obligation to follow its prior holdings) than whether defendants in state courts may be convicted by a less-than-unanimous jury. This aspect of the opinion has been widely discussed (see analysis here, here, here, and here), and foreshadows the justices’ likely battle over an upcoming reproductive rights case. Since the divergent perspectives on stare decisis have been covered elsewhere, I will consider another issue that split the justices: the legal relevance of the nonunanimous jury law’s Jim Crow origins.
First, a pop quiz
Did North Carolina ever allow non unanimous jury verdicts in criminal trials? Read on for the answer.
The facts and procedural history of the case
Evangelisto Ramos was charged with a second-degree murder in New Orleans in 2014. He maintained his innocence and invoked his right to a jury trial. At the conclusion of the trial, ten jurors found Mr. Ramos guilty and two jurors found him not guilty. In the 48 states (including North Carolina) and federal court where all jurors must agree on a guilty verdict to convict a defendant, this would have resulted in a hung jury and a mistrial. Instead, because he was tried in Louisiana (before voters repealed the nonunanimous jury provision in 2019), Mr. Ramos was convicted and sentenced to life in prison without the possibility of parole. Appellate courts in Louisiana affirmed the conviction, relying on Apodaca v. Oregon, 406 U.S. 404 (1972), which had declined to extend the Sixth Amendment right to a unanimous jury to the states under the Fourteenth Amendment. The Supreme Court granted certiorari and reversed Mr. Ramos’s conviction.
Mr. Ramos’s Sixth Amendment challenge
Mr. Ramos asserted that the nonunanimous jury verdict violated his Sixth Amendment right to a unanimous jury. His argument rested on the historical and continued meaning of the Sixth Amendment right to a trial by an impartial jury, which provides that “[i]n all criminal prosecutions, the accused shall enjoy the right to a speedy and public trial, by an impartial jury[.]” He argued that the impartial jury guarantee, at the time the Sixth Amendment was adopted in 1789, included the right to a unanimous jury verdict. Neither party disputed that the right to a unanimous jury verdict was central to the jury trial right at common law, dating back to 1367. See Douglas G. Smith, The Historical and Constitutional Contexts of Jury Reform, 25 Hofstra L. Rev. 377, 397 (1996). The U.S. Supreme Court has referenced that history on several occasions, at one point describing the common law right to a unanimous jury as so widely known that “[n]o authorities are needed to sustain this proposition.” Am. Publ’g Co. v. Fisher, 166 U.S. 464, 468 (1897). And the Supreme Court had already agreed that the purpose and effect of the impartial jury guarantee of the Sixth Amendment was to codify the common law meaning of the jury right, including the right to a unanimous verdict. See, e.g., Patton v. United States, 281 U. S. 276, 288 (1930). The only question before the Ramos court was the applicability of that aspect of the right to the states—whether the right was incorporated under the Fourteenth Amendment to bind states as well as the federal government. The biggest hurdle for Mr. Ramos to overcome was that the earlier decision, Apodaca, already answered this question in the negative.
Nonunanimous jury verdicts sound race-neutral: what’s race got to do with it?
Justice Gorsuch begins his opinion, in a portion joined by a narrow majority of the justices (Justices Breyer, Ginsburg, Sotomayor, and Kavanaugh), with a history lesson not on the Sixth Amendment but on nonunanimous juries in Louisiana. It is an ugly history, revealing a white supremacist backlash to the growing rights and political power of black people at the end of the nineteenth century. The move away from unanimous juries in Louisiana emerged in response to constitutional, statutory, and judicial efforts to secure the rights of black people to serve on juries through the adoption of the Fourteenth Amendment in 1868, the Civil Rights Act of 1875, and the U.S. Supreme Court’s decision in Strauder v. West Virginia, 100 U.S. 303 (1880) (holding that racial discrimination in jury selection compromises the right of trial by jury and violates the Equal Protection Clause). Justice Gorsuch explains that the nonunanimous jury provision originated in Louisiana’s 1898 constitutional convention, the purpose of which, according to one committee chairman, was to “establish the supremacy of the white race.” Ramos v. Louisiana, Slip. Op. at 2. Alongside other Jim Crow provisions intended to disenfranchise black people, including a poll tax and combined literacy and property ownership test, the nonunanimous jury provision targeted black people without explicitly naming this intent in its text. “With a careful eye on racial demographics, the convention delegates sculpted a facially race-neutral rule permitting 10-to-2 verdicts in order to ensure that African-American juror service would be meaningless.” Slip Op. at 2 (internal quotations omitted).
Justice Kavanaugh explains why nonunanimous jury provisions limit the influence of black jurors on the outcome of criminal trials:
Then and now, non-unanimous juries can silence the voices and negate the votes of black jurors, especially in cases with black defendants or black victims, and only one or two black jurors. The 10 jurors “can simply ignore the views of their fellow panel members of a different race or class.” Johnson v. Louisiana, 406 U. S. 356, 397 (1972) (Stewart, J., dissenting). That reality—and the resulting perception of unfairness and racial bias—can undermine confidence in and respect for the criminal justice system. The non-unanimous jury operates much the same as the unfettered peremptory challenge, a practice that for many decades likewise functioned as an engine of discrimination against black defendants, victims, and jurors. In effect, the non-unanimous jury allows backdoor and unreviewable peremptory strikes against up to 2 of the 12 jurors.
Slip Op. at 35 (Kavanaugh, J., concurring in part).
In 1974, Louisiana readopted its nonunanimous jury provision. Why? The justices don’t seem sure. Justice Gorsuch briefly concludes that “it’s hard to say why these laws persist”; Justice Kavanaugh speculates that the continued reliance on nonunanimous juries “may have been motivated by neutral principles (or just by inertia)”; and Justice Alito notes that the stated purpose of the nonunanimous jury provision in 1974 was judicial efficiency and, in the debate, “no mention was made of race.” Slip Op. at 3 (Alito, J., dissenting). But Justice Sotomayor observes that when it comes to old laws originally motivated by racial animus, it is often the case that “States’ legislatures never truly grapple[] with the laws’ sordid history in reenacting them.” Slip Op. at 33 (Sotomayor, J., concurring in part). She finds that Louisiana’s only effort to do so came not in 1974 but just last year, when Louisiana voters approved a 2019 referendum repealing the nonunanimous jury provision. The campaign for a unanimous jury right focused in part on the racist origins and continuing racially disparate outcomes of the nonunanimous jury law.
Raise your hand if you think that the Jim Crow origins of Louisiana’s nonunanimous jury provision is important to consider in this case
Not all nine justices think we should consider this history. Only five do. Four justices share Justice Gorsuch’s perspective that the racist history of Louisiana’s nonunanimous jury verdict law matters here. Concurring in most of Justice Gorsuch’s opinion, Justice Sotomayor writes separately to stress how important the Jim Crow history is to the invalidity of nonunanimous juries. Justice Kavanaugh also spends part of his lengthy concurrence discussing the significance of the racism that gave rise to nonunanimous juries. Justice Thomas ignores the Jim Crow history altogether, and Justice Alito, joined by Justice Kagan and Chief Justice Roberts, seems more offended by the majority’s audacity to observe that racism underpinned the nonunanimous jury provision than by the racism itself. Slip Op. at 62-66 (Alito, J., dissenting).
It may sound unremarkable that five justices in this case examine the racist history underlying Louisiana’s nonunanimous jury provision. In reviewing the constitutionality of a provision arising out of a white supremacist state constitutional convention, wouldn’t the Court have to reckon with that history? Certainly, if Mr. Ramos had raised an equal protection challenge to his nonunanimous jury verdict, the Court would have been squarely presented with the legal question of whether the nonunanimous jury provision was unlawful because it was motivated by a discriminatory purpose and had a discriminatory effect. But outside the equal protection context, the U.S. Supreme Court has marginalized the relevance of racist intent when such a consideration is not an essential element of a defendant’s legal claim, for example, when a traffic stop is challenged as racially motivated in violation of the Fourth Amendment. See, e.g., Whren v. United States, 517 U.S. 806, 813 (1996) (“[T]he Constitution prohibits selective enforcement of the law based on considerations such as race. But the constitutional basis for objecting to intentionally discriminatory application of laws is the Equal Protection Clause, not the Fourth Amendment. Subjective intentions play no role in ordinary, probable-cause Fourth Amendment analysis.”).
Why did a majority of the Court look so closely at this history in Ramos, and what exactly did they do with it? It is easy enough to note that five justices think that the racist origins of the law matter here and four justices apparently think they don’t. The more difficult question is how and why that history matters. How, if at all, does Jim Crow history influence the justices’ resolution of the legal questions before them in Ramos?
The answer is elusive. Justice Gorsuch highlights the racist origins of the law and criticizes the Apodaca plurality for ignoring that history, but in a footnote concedes that his discussion of Louisiana’s white supremacist constitutional convention is dicta, as nonunanimous juries would violate the Sixth Amendment impartial jury guarantee whether or not they were designed to diminish the influence of black jurors. Justice Sotomayor emphasizes that “the racially biased origins of the Louisiana and Oregon laws uniquely matter here,” but what does it mean legally to “matter”? Does the history matter because it serves as important context; because the Court has an ethical obligation to acknowledge painful aspects of our history (a “never again” perspective); or does it somehow factor into the resolution of the questions before the Court? She does not detail how the Jim Crow origins of Louisiana’s nonunanimous juries affect the Court’s analysis of the legal issues. She implies that an equal protection claim may have succeeded here, referencing the analogous case of United States v. Fordice, 505 U. S. 717, 729 (1992), which held that policies “‘traceable’ to a State’s de jure racial segregation and that still ‘have discriminatory effects’ offend the Equal Protection Clause.”
Justice Kavanaugh alone specifies how the origins of Louisiana’s nonunanimous juries influence the resolution of this case. He concludes that, once the court has determined that the correct resolution of the issues conflicts with a prior court holding (here, the Apodaca ruling), the court is more justified in departing from precedent when it has caused “significant negative jurisprudential or real-world consequences.” Slip Op. at 42 (Kavanaugh, J., concurring in part). The nonunanimous jury provision “tolerates and reinforces a practice that is thoroughly racist in its origins and has continuing racially discriminatory effects,” a significant negative consequence. This framework brings the Jim Crow history into the stare decisis analysis, not the determination of the scope of the Sixth Amendment right to a unanimous jury, or whether, under the Fourteenth Amendment, this right binds the states.
Why does the Jim Crow discussion feature so prominently? Is it easier for justices to confront vestiges of racism (a la Ramos) than to confront contemporary allegations of more widespread racial bias (a la Whren)? Or perhaps the justices are more likely to consider racism as relevant when ruling on Sixth Amendment challenges involving the right to a jury trial? Recently, in Pena-Rodriguez v. Colorado, 137 S. Ct. 855, 867 (2017), the U.S. Supreme Court held that in cases involving evidence of racial bias in juror deliberations, the rule preventing the court from hearing juror testimony about statements made during deliberations must yield so that the court may consider whether the alleged racial bias violated the defendant’s Sixth Amendment right to a fair trial. That was not an equal protection case, but a case concerning the right to a fair and impartial jury, and the Court’s decision rested (as Justice Kavanaugh explains in Ramos) on a recognition of “the imperative to purge racial prejudice from the administration of justice generally and from the jury system in particular.” Id. at 13–14 (quoting Pena-Rodriguez and collecting cases). So, a working theory: when a defendant asserts a Fourth Amendment right, racial bias generally doesn’t matter, but when asserting a Sixth Amendment right, it might? Or maybe, as my colleague Shea Denning has considered and Justice Ginsburg has suggested, Whren was wrongly decided?
The bottom line here is that a majority of the court concluded that it is important to consider Jim Crow history when ruling on whether the unanimous verdict aspect of the Sixth Amendment right to a jury trial applies to the states. Although the justices in the majority do not agree on how this history factors into the analysis, the decision suggests that Jim Crow origins may support the invalidation of laws even outside of equal protection challenges.
What does this mean in states like North Carolina where jury unanimity was already guaranteed?
The holding in Ramos does not have immediate implications for North Carolina, where people accused of crimes already had a right to a unanimous jury. However, it raises interesting questions about the possibility that Jim Crow laws may have evolved into current law without careful examination or reconsideration. Kavanaugh asserts that the “nonunanimous jury is today the last of Louisiana’s Jim Crow laws.” (Slip. Op. Kavanaugh, J., concurring, at 48.) Assuming that this is true, what about in other states? What about here?
In 1898, the year of Louisiana’s constitutional convention, North Carolina saw similar white supremacist political activity, propaganda, and related violence, including the only successful political coup in United States history, in which white supremacists overthrew the city government of Wilmington, killing numerous black residents, forcing the resignation of the mayor, police chief, and aldermen, and burning down the headquarters of a black newspaper. Caleb Crain, City Limits: What a white-supremacist coup looks like, The New Yorker, April 27, 2020. As in Louisiana, “white supremacists went on to alter state law so as to disenfranchise black people[;]” while there were “more than a hundred and twenty-five thousand registered black voters in North Carolina in 1896 . . . only six thousand or so were still on the books by 1902.” Id. at 67. See also Thomas W. Frampton, The Jim Crow Jury, 71 Vanderbilt Law Review 1593, 1613-14 fns 118, 123, 124 (2019) (quoting articles published in 1898 and 1899 in the Semi-Weekly Messenger, a Wilmington newspaper, making white supremacist appeals for nonunanimous juries, one of which suggests that nonunanimous jury verdicts will reduce the need for lynchings). Are any of the laws passed in this era and motivated by this campaign of white supremacy still on the books?
The answer, almost certainly, is yes. Consider the North Carolina law making it a felony to vote when ineligible, even if the voter is unaware that he or she is ineligible to vote. This law dates back nearly unaltered to this same political effort to disenfranchise black voters around the turn of the twentieth century. Are there others? Some aspects of jury selection, including the use of peremptory strikes, have been historically entangled with discrimination. See April Anderson, Peremptory Challenges at the Turn of the Nineteenth Century: Development of Modern Jury Selection Strategies as Seen in Practitioners’ Trial Manuals 16 Stan. J. C.R. & C.L. 1 (2020). Historians at UNC are working on documenting North Carolina’s Jim Crow Laws, which may help identify others still in operation.
Justice Sotomayor’s concurrence in Ramos cautions that we may be governed by dated laws, in North Carolina and elsewhere, that have been reenacted or maintained without meaningful consideration of their Jim Crow origins and purpose. At least some of our legal architecture is built on the same troubling historical foundations described in Ramos. The splintered Ramos opinion does not provide a roadmap for resolving legal challenges related to Jim Crow laws—outside the usual equal protection approach—but a majority of the justices insist that this history cannot be ignored.
About that pop quiz
Yes, North Carolina briefly allowed non-unanimous jury verdicts in the 17th century. See Williams v. Florida, 399 U.S. 78, 98 n.45 (1970). I don’t know what motivated the adoption of nonunanimous juries in North Carolina or the return to unanimity. If you know more about this history, please leave a comment, and of course, feel free to comment on any other issues raised by the Ramos decision.
The post Ramos v. Louisiana and the Jim Crow Origins of Nonunanimous Juries appeared first on North Carolina Criminal Law.
Ramos v. Louisiana and the Jim Crow Origins of Nonunanimous Juries published first on https://immigrationlawyerto.tumblr.com/
0 notes