#SENSA 338
Explore tagged Tumblr posts
Text
SENSA338
SENSA338 KOMPITABLE TERBARU DENGAN PAKET LENGKAP
0 notes
Text
To be more precise, Whitehead defines eternal objects as follows: âany entity whose conceptual recognition does not involve a necessary reference to any definite actual entities of the temporal world is called an âeternal objectââ (1929/1978, 44). This means that eternal objects include sensory qualities, like colors (blueness or greenness) and tactile sensations (softness or roughness), conceptual abstractions like shapes (a helix, or a dodecahedron) and numbers (seven, or the square root of minus two), moral qualities (like bravery or cowardice), physical fundamentals (like gravitational attraction or electric charge), and much more besides. An eternal object can also be âa determinate way in which a feeling can feel. It is an emotion, or an intensity, or an adversion, or an aversion, or a pleasure, or a painâ (291). âSensaââor what today are more commonly called âqualiaââare âthe lowest category of eternal objectsâ (114). But there are also âcomplex eternal objectsâ that have the simpler ones as components. In this way, affects or emotions are eternal objects; and so are âcontrasts, or patterns,â or anything else that can âexpress a manner of relatedness between other eternal objectsâ (114). There is, in fact, âan indefinite progression of categories, as we proceed from âcontrastsâ to âcontrasts of contrasts,â and on indefinitely to higher grades of contrastsâ (22). The levels and complexities proliferate, without limit. But regardless of level, eternal objects are ideal abstractions that nevertheless (in contrast to Platonic forms) can only be encountered within experience, when they are âselectedâ and âfeltâ by particular actual occasions.
Whiteheadâs use of the word âeternalâ might seem to be a strange move, in the context of a philosophy grounded in events, becomings, and continual change and novelty. And indeed, as if acknowledging this, he remarks that, âif the term âeternal objectsâ is disliked, the term âpotentialsâ would be suitableâ instead (1929/1978, 149). But if Whitehead prefers to retain the appellation âeternal objects,â this is precisely because he seeksâlike Nietzsche, Bergson, and Deleuzeâto reject the Platonic separation between eternity and time, the binary opposition that sets a higher world of permanence and perfection (âa static, spiritual heavenâ) against an imperfect lower world of flux (209). The two instead must continually interpenetrate. For âpermanence can be snatched only out of flux; and the passing moment can find its adequate intensity only by its submission to permanence. Those who would disjoin the two elements can find no interpretation of patent factsâ (338). Actual entities continually perish; but the relations between them, or the patterns that they make, tend to recur, or endure. Thus âit is not âsubstanceâ which is permanent, but âform.ââ And even forms do not subsist absolutely, but continually âsuffer changing relationsâ (29). In asserting this, Whitehead converts Plato from idealism to empiricism, just as he similarly converts Spinoza, Leibniz, Hume, and Kant.
Steven Shaviro, Without Criteria
33 notes
¡
View notes