Tumgik
#Plumber Point Clare
bluewatsons · 4 years
Text
Mohammed Abouelleil Rashe, In Defense of Madness: The Problem of Disability, 44 J Med & Philosophy 150 (2019)
Abstract
At a time when different groups in society are achieving notable gains in respect and rights, activists in mental health and proponents of mad positive approaches, such as Mad Pride, are coming up against considerable challenges. A particular issue is the commonly held view that madness is inherently disabling and cannot form the grounds for identity or culture. This paper responds to the challenge by developing two bulwarks against the tendency to assume too readily the view that madness is inherently disabling: the first arises from the normative nature of disability judgments, and the second arises from the implications of political activism in terms of being a social subject. In the process of arguing for these two bulwarks, the paper explores the basic structure of the social model of disability in the context of debates on naturalism and normativism, the applicability of the social model to madness, and the difference between physical and mental disabilities in terms of the unintelligibility often attributed to the latter.
I. Introduction
For a number of decades, there have been considerable attempts to develop positive narratives of mental health phenomena, narratives that can counteract the pervasive, negative views in society and the profession of psychiatry.1 The context in which these attempts were and are made is a burgeoning movement(s) of activism and advocacy in mental health. A recent chapter in this activism is Mad Pride, a movement and discourse that pose a direct and radical challenge to the social norms and values underpinning views on “mental illness.”2 Mad Pride discourse rejects the language of “illness” and “disorder,” reclaims the term “mad,” and replaces its negative connotations with more positive understandings. It reverses the customary understanding of madness as illness in favor of the view that madness can be grounds for identity and culture. In addition, Mad positive approaches and framings abound in the writings of activists: phenomena of madness such as states of heightened sensory awareness, visions and voices, and the ability to perceive complexity and significance in everyday experiences are considered special and valuable, and not indicators of psychopathology. Their value is sometimes taken to arise from the creative, artistic, cultural, and spiritual potential afforded by these experiences.
Mad Pride discourse recognizes that madness can also be associated with distress and difficulties in social functioning. This Janus-faced nature of madness—at once a source of creativity and suffering—led to the formulation that individual traits and sensitivities are “dangerous gifts” that require cultivation and care.3 Yet, it is the question of distress and disability that has proved to be a sticking point for Mad Pride discourse and for mad positive approaches in general: how can one advance a positive framing of that which appears to be inherently negative? This criticism has been expressed strongly by service users as well as academics. Clare Allan, an ex-patient who has written about her experiences with mental health services, argues that there is nothing about “mental illness” of which to be proud. Although she recognizes the stigma faced by mental health patients, she understands Mad Pride as essentially a tactic to bolster the self-esteem of service users who, for years, have been subjected to stigma and disrespect in society and degrading treatment by services; she writes:
Mental illness is not an identity. Nor is it something I wish to celebrate . . . Mental illness is ruthless, indiscriminate and destructive. It is also an illness. It is certainly not a weakness, but nor is it a sign of a special “artistic” sensitivity. It affected Van Gogh, as it does bus drivers, plumbers, teachers, older people and children. Winston Churchill was reportedly manic-depressive, if so, it’s a diagnosis he shares with my friend Cathy, a mother of two from Peckham. Mental illness is an illness, just as cancer is an illness; and people die from both. (Allan, 2006)
A similar criticism can be found in the academic literature. Jost (2009, 2) writes that “mental illnesses” are not “different ways of processing information or emotion; they are disorders in the capacities for processing information or emotion.” It is absurd, she argues, to urge people to embrace such conditions and regard them positively. In making this point, Jost (2009, 2) draws a distinction between conditions that are disabling because the physical and social environment fails to accommodate variations in traits and characteristics, and “mental illnesses” that are “inherently negative” and “will always cause suffering” even if stigma and disadvantage were to be eliminated. Perring (2009) writes that for some of those who object to the movement, the analogy with Black Pride or Gay Pride—an analogy made in Mad Pride discourse—can only go so far as none of these are intrinsically disabling features of a person while mental illnesses” tend to be seen as such. That is why, he notes, it would be equally bizarre to have a Cancer Pride movement. Such views, no doubt, have wide currency among many clinicians who see every day in the clinic the effects of “mental illness”: social and functional deterioration, loss of friends and family, and the distress of extreme mental states.
There is, therefore, a challenge facing Mad Pride discourse and mad positive approaches: the problem of distress and disability. In this paper, I respond to the problem of disability by developing two bulwarks against the tendency to adopt, too readily, the (medical) view that madness is inherently disabling: (1) the normative basis of disability judgments; (2) the implications of political activism in terms of being a social subject. To delineate the scope of my argument, I begin with two disclaimers: first, my concern in this paper is disability and not distress. The former, on an initial reading, consists in limitations to/impairments of everyday functioning and participation. The latter—distress—concerns affective states such as fear, anxiety, or sadness. The two can be connected, of course; intense fear can impact on functioning, and disability can engender anxiety. This connection will be noted as required, but the two concepts raise different issues and require separate consideration.4 Second, my purpose is not to argue against the medical model of disability but against the tendency to assume it too readily in the case of madness. I begin by clarifying the criticism of Mad Pride and mad positive approaches.
II. Clarifying the Criticism
The problem of disability, as it emerges through the aforementioned criticisms of Mad Pride, can be more accurately stated as follows:
“Mental illness” is associated with disability.
This association is not contingent: disability is intrinsic to mental illness, which means that the various limitations experienced by individuals with those “conditions” are a result of the “conditions” and not an intolerant or unaccommodating society.
By contrast, so the argument would go, the limitations experienced by gay individuals were/are a result of a homophobic society that denied them equal rights and the right to be themselves. Once we correct for social discrimination and oppression, the limitations that gay individuals face will reduce.
In brief, the criticism can be formulated as follows: even in a utopian world where there is absolutely no discrimination and a surplus of well-meaning regard that people show toward each other, “mental illness” will still reduce the well-being of those afflicted.5 To be clear from the outset, this statement cannot be intended as an empirical claim, not only because there are no studies of the fate of “mental illness” in utopia but because the proof demanded for this claim to work requires that the phenomena in question remain disabling for afflicted individuals once all socially discriminating and negative conditions have been removed. The problem here is that it will never be possible to assert that one has concluded the investigation, as it will not be possible to know if social conditions are the best they could be, assuming we can even agree on what “best” means. Given that it is not intended as an empirical claim, what exactly is the basis for it? To gain some further ground here, we can consider a possible response to this criticism, one that appears in the writings of some activists.
The response is to affirm that what is referred to as “mental illness” is a variation on human experiences and ways of being. The reason these variations may lead to problems in functioning has to do with a social world that is not set up to accommodate them and not due to a “disorder” or some intrinsic malfunction:
Most mental illnesses are seen as disorders because they prevent the person from functioning properly in the social world we have set up for ourselves . . . If the majority of the population was bipolar, things would be set up to accommodate them, and those without bipolar “symptoms” would struggle to fit in and understand the world. Is failure to hold up to the expectations of other people really a disorder? (Polvora, 2011, 4)
Both the criticism and the response to it purport to specify the locus of the problem: the former locates the cause of disability in the individual—in the “mental illness” to be precise—and the latter locates it in a society designed only to accommodate a particular norm. Essentially, then, the two positions here reflect a “medical” versus a “social” understanding of the limitations associated with madness. To arbitrate between them, I visit the social model of disability, a framework that has been substantially worked out in Disability Theory and can help make sense of this dispute.
III. Models of Disability
According to standard definitions, disability is comprised of a physical or mental impairment associated with long-term limitations on the ability to perform daily activities.6 For example, blindness, according to this framework, would be an impairment—or, for a less value-laden term, a variation in human functioning—that ordinarily would limit the person’s ability for personal and social functioning and participation. The priority given either to impairment or to social context in generating limitations gave rise to a number of disability models, the most prominent of which are the medical and the social models. The medical (individual) model emphasizes variations as the primary cause of limitation and prescribes medical correction and/or financial compensation. The social model, endorsed in some form by many disability activists and theoreticians, emphasizes that limitations arise from a physical and social environment designed and conducted in such a way that excludes or does not take into account individuals with variations in traits or characteristics (Oliver, 1990, 1996).7 The social model shifts attention to restrictive and exclusionary conditions in society and prescribes various sorts of accommodations to address this. In the case of sensory impairments/variations, for example blindness, accommodations can include practical adjustments such as tactile and audio signage.
It is important at this point to introduce some complexity into the notion of limitation in view of the kinds of actions involved. Nordenfelt (1997) distinguishes basic actions from generated actions. A basic action, such as moving a limb, is a simple and primary action that constitutes the first step in the chain that ends with complex, or generated, action (Nordenfelt, 1997, 611). The latter are actions describable at the level of the person in terms of overarching goals such as “writing a book” or “making a chair.” To clarify the notion of basic action, it will help to see it not in predefined terms but as something that becomes apparent by its absence. In this way, we can avoid having to ground the notion in an account of species-typical natural functioning and can leave it open to individual variation. Further, the notion of basic “action” needs to be broadened to incorporate other aspects of our fundamental abilities that are not ordinarily thought of as actions. For example, a certain level of concentration is required to be able to focus on a task. Concentration, according to the account advanced here, is not a basic “action” but a basic “ability” that underpins much of what we do.
Ordinarily, we become aware of the basic nature of some of our abilities when we are thwarted in realizing our complex goals. Ideally, the body is the medium through which we project and realize our intentions in the world. It remains in the background as a transparent medium until, for some reason, its interference with our complex goals renders salient a particular aspect or function. It can be a painful limb, impaired concentration, poor vision, or a heightened state of anxiety. All of these can be considered within the scope of basic abilities in the sense that they are disruptions to the taken for granted background of our complex activity in the world and become salient when they hold us back.8 The point at which this occurs is as personal as it is cultural, and we need not for this view refer to an account of natural function.
On this basis, we can distinguish two levels of limitation. The first level consists in the basic inabilities (typified in disability models as impairments or variations) that become salient when our complex activity in the world is disrupted. 9 The second level consists in the disruptions to the complex activity itself: the inability to work, socialize, or go to the market. Now, though an impairment constitutes a limitation at the basic level—a blind person cannot see, a broken limb cannot bear weight—it is not by itself sufficient for limitations at the level of complex activity. Complex actions are always performed in some physical and social environment, and the extent to which we can realize our goals depends, in part, on the match between the environment and our (in)abilities (see Amundson, 1992, 109–10).10 So, though a blind person may be unable to see (a limitation at the level of basic abilities), his inability to realize employment (a limitation at the level of complex action) can be addressed through specially designed working quarters that take into account his specific sensory abilities. Of course, one may wish to correct for the basic inability (the impairment)—to correct for loss of vision or hearing for example—but where that is not possible (technologically) or desired (e.g., Deaf Pride), then the variation/environment interaction can be scrutinized for impediments to the realization of specific complex goals.
Another helpful way to cash out the distinction between these two levels of limitation is in terms of the extent to which disadvantages are conditional on/produced by the social context. Amundson and Tresky (2007, 544) define the terms as follows:
Conditional Disadvantages of Impairment (CDIs): Disadvantages that are experienced by people with impairments, but which are produced by the social context in which those people live.
Unconditional Disadvantages of Impairment (UDIs): Disadvantages that are experienced by people with impairments, but which are produced irrespective of their social context.
Mapped onto the two levels of limitations specified earlier, basic inabilities would be unconditional whereas disruptions to complex activities would be conditional. Although I see a place for the distinction as such, I would not put it this strongly, as the notion of an absolutely unconditional disadvantage does not work. As I argued previously, a basic inability is made salient in the context of failing to achieve a complex action. The latter itself is relative to physical and social environmental contexts and hence is, in part, conditional upon them. So, it is more accurate to see this distinction as a matter of degree and not kind: as a distinction concerning the proximity of a particular description of disadvantage to one’s physical and mental states as opposed to the environment in which one is pursuing goals.11
The importance of the distinction between conditional and unconditional disadvantages is that it serves to limit the “oversocialisation” of the radical form of the social model of disability, which appears to deny a role for impairment in generating disadvantage (Terzi, 2004, 153). With this distinction in place, it becomes possible to argue, for example, that while a deaf person may be unable to hear and may not be able to listen to music, these particular “limitations” flow from the impairment/variation and are separate from the restrictions he or she may face in finding employment or watching the news when no alternative form of communication, such as sign language, is made available.12 The former are basic inabilities—whether or not they are undesirable—and the latter are the limitations caused by an unaccommodating social environment. As Amundson and Tresky (2007, 544) note, in disability rights discourse unconditional disadvantages “are taken as brute facts of human variation” and are not considered within the scope of disability claims and campaigning. Similarly, the social model—writes Oliver (2004, 22), the person credited with its introduction—“is not about the personal experience of impairment but the collective experience of disablement.”
Having made this distinction, it is important to note that there is no hard and fast way of drawing the line between unconditional and conditional disadvantages. The distinction is worked out in practice, leaning heavily on disabled peoples’ experiences and on what exactly the demand for social accommodation is about in the context of wider debates on these issues (see Amundson and Tresky, 2007, 553). Yet, the problem with the medical model of disability, and with the criticisms of Mad Pride described earlier, is that this distinction—if it is made at all—appears to lean too heavily on one side, with all or most limitations considered to arise from the impairment/variation. Such medical models conflate the two levels of limitation discerned earlier or recognize them as distinct but put too much emphasis on basic inabilities over disruption to complex activity. The area of contention then lies precisely at the boundary where what is put forward by disability rights activists as a conditional disadvantage is seen by advocates of the medical model as an unconditional disadvantage flowing from, or intrinsic to, the impairment itself. It is the latter, medical view that I consider problematic and to which I now turn.
IV. Naturalism, Normativism, and Disability
Critics of the medical model of disability have argued that the claim that limitations are “caused” by the impairment—that, say, not being able to access information is caused by a person’s sensory impairments—presupposes a naturalistic view of function (Amundson, 2000). Naturalism is the view that norms of physical and mental functioning can be objectively determined. Two well-known naturalist accounts have been put forth by Christopher Boorse and Jerome Wakefield. For Boorse (1997), a normal function of a part or process of an individual is a statistically typical contribution by it to the individual’s survival and reproduction. Statistically normal function is determined relative to the individual’s reference class, which is the appropriate segment of the species as defined by age and sex.13 For Wakefield (1992, 384), the natural function of a mechanism is the function for which it has been designed (selected) in evolution; it is “part of the evolutionary explanation of the existence and structure of the mechanism.” For example, the heart pumps blood, the legs move our body, and the visual system conveys perceptual information about the world: these are natural functions of the respective organs; they are what the organs were designed to do.
On the basis of their accounts of natural function, Boorse and Wakefield can then purport to specify physical or mental dysfunction in value-free terms as deviation from natural function. Both also recognize that that is not sufficient by itself to delineate the conditions that should be treated. For Boorse (2011, 28) and Wakefield (1992), a further evaluative component is required, which consists in the evaluation of this dysfunction as harmful in light of personal, social, and medical norms and values. On Wakefield’s formulation, disorder becomes a harmful dysfunction or—which amounts to the same thing for our purposes here—a harmful impairment. With this kind of reasoning, a blind person would have a dysfunction/impairment in the visual apparatus that, if associated with harm, would qualify the condition as a disorder. And given that according to naturalistic accounts function is a matter of objectively determined natural facts—with dysfunction being a deviation from normal function—then the limitation, the harm, that may arise from this is referred back to the dysfunction and not to a deficiency in the design of the physical and social environments relative to the functional abilities of different persons. This is because the person with a dysfunction, on this view, lies outside the range of normal functional abilities, and he or she lies outside this range not due to some inconsiderate value judgment but by the facts of human nature.
The problem with naturalistic theories, and therefore with the foregoing argument, is that attempts to define dysfunction in value-free terms have not been successful. This debate has been well rehearsed by several philosophers and I will only state their conclusions.14
Since its inception, Boorse’s theory has been subject to a lively interchange and many objections. Of particular relevance here are accusations of implicit normativism in both the notion of statistically normal function and the reference class against which this is to be assessed. With regard to the former, Bolton (2008, 113) points out that statistical (ab)normality does not by itself tell us at what point on a continuous distribution curve “deviance from the mean become(s) subnormal function.” Factors that in fact do underlie this judgment are those associated with the value component: harm and functional limitations as judged by personal and, more broadly, social values and norms. As a principle purporting to provide a factual basis for discerning normal from subnormal function, statistical normality does not work. With regard to reference classes, Kingma (2007, 2013) argues that Boorse’s account requires that he specify the reference classes appropriate to an assessment of health. Otherwise, any condition can be rendered healthy if we devise a reference class that shows it in a good light. For example, if we were to allow for a reference class of “uncommonly heavy drinkers,” then liver functions that would otherwise be considered abnormal would no longer be so, and those heavy drinkers, according to Boorse’s account, would be considered healthy (Kingma, 2007, 128). Boorse, therefore, needs to provide an account of the appropriate reference classes, and he needs to do so in a value-free, noncircular way, i.e., without introducing values into what is supposed to be a fact-based definition of normal function, and without presupposing the distinction he is trying to prove between health and disease (Kingma, 2007). As Kingma (2007, 2013) argues, Boorse’s account cannot provide this.
Wakefield’s harmful dysfunction analysis of disorder has also met with serious objections. Dysfunction, as noted earlier, is deviation from the natural function of a mechanism: the function that explains, in evolutionary terms, the mechanism’s existence and design. For our purposes here, the most relevant objection to Wakefield’s analysis of dysfunction is that which questions its presumed factual basis. For Wakefield, the norms underpinning natural function are natural (evolutionary) norms to be contrasted with social (cultivated) norms (Bolton, 2008, 124). The former underpin the objective status of dysfunction and the latter feature in the harm component. According to Bolton (2013), it is no longer possible to maintain a clear distinction between what is natural/innate and what is social/cultivated. It is now generally accepted that psychological functions are a product of an interaction between several factors: socialisation processes and genetic inheritance, complicated by individual differences and choice (Bolton, 2013, 442–3). These factors are not separable through the science we currently possess (Bolton, 2013, 442–3). Yet without a clear distinction, Wakefield’s account cannot tag exclusively onto a fact of our evolutionary nature in its bid to provide a value-free account of dysfunction.
If we accept the criticisms of these two leading naturalist theories, we can conclude that it has not proven possible to define function and dysfunction in value-free terms. We may accept this conclusion yet continue the search for a value-free, theoretical concept of function. An alternative position is to take seriously the value-ladenness of the relevant concepts and see where this may lead us. It will lead us to various forms of normativism about function. Here, descriptions of normal function are made in terms of what is good or bad, desirable or undesirable for an agent in the context of specific life situations and environments, in the present or a projected future. Those descriptions, though not pretending to have an objective standpoint in nature, are not any less “real” than naturalistic accounts: the core values that inform our lives, the projects we engage in, and the futures we plan are very serious matters. Indeed, it is a reflection of their seriousness that we tend to refer to those aspects of our abilities that may prevents us from pursuing them as “diseases” or “disorders.” But, the apparent objectivity of these terms should not obscure that they signal a normative and not a natural limit; they signal the limit of what a person and/or society considers normal, valuable, or good. These notions are set against a background of abilities that are considered the norm, in the sense of being the taken for granted foundations of a particular way of life in a particular social and physical environment. This has implications on how we can talk about disability.
It will help at this point to recall the problem that led us here. It was borne out of the need to arbitrate between the medical and social views on the origin of the limitations associated with variations in function. Advocates of the medical model consider most of the limitations to be unconditional, i.e., intrinsic to the dysfunction/impairment/variation itself. Given the prior analysis, we have a different way of understanding this claim. When we witness a person struggling to achieve some complex goal, we may refer this back to some dysfunction in his or her abilities. Now, we can see that the limit drawn by our reference to dysfunction is a normative and not a natural limit. Hence, when we say that a dysfunction (or an impairment or variation) is intrinsically disabling, we need also to give an account of the norms, values, and contexts by which we were driven to make this claim, and to come to terms with that being the basis of our judgment. The importance of remaining cognizant of this point is that in its absence we would not even occasion the need to perhaps examine those norms, values, and contexts and see if they can be modified in such a way that would reflect positively on that person’s ability to function and thrive in society through various sorts of adjustments. This would act as a bulwark against the gratuitous individualization of the difficulties others face, and the powerful tendency to medicalize their predicament instead of coming to terms with the social solutions that can be put in place, bearing in mind that that is what the activists are asking for.
Before proceeding, a final clarification: this argument for a normative reading of disability judgments does not entail that we must in each case employ the social model, evidently not; in many cases addressing limitations through medical correction or, more generally, intervention at the personal level will be recommended. What it does mean, however, is that the judgment as to whether we should intervene at the individual or social level cannot be made through recourse to some account of natural function and dysfunction, but by pragmatic as well as ethical factors including considerations of efficiency, safety, equality, and justice to name a few.
V. Applying the Social Model to Madness
Having established the normative nature of disability judgments and having developed the first bulwark against the tendency to view certain variations/impairments in functioning as inherently disabling, it remains to be seen just how the social model can be applied to madness. In the ensuing discussion, note that the concern is with conditions that are long-lasting, have a substantial effect on daily activity, and where treatment is either not desired or not possible, i.e., we are concerned with “disabilities” and not acute or self-limiting problems.
Applying the social model to madness is not new; activists and academics have written about the potential and the problems of doing so. The disability movement has achieved some progress in making salient the contributions of the physical and social environments to generating limitations, with many accommodations to address this now enshrined in law. Developing a social model of madness in keeping with the social model of disability is seen as a way of counteracting the “medicalized individual approach” that is dominant in society and mental health institutions (Beresford, 2005; see also Mulvany, 2000). Resistance to this proposal has come from both sides. Some psychiatric survivors/service users refuse to be associated with disability discourse, as they do not consider themselves to have an impairment, nor do they want to be associated with the “pathologising” implications of the term “impairment” (see Beresford, 2000; Beresford et al., 2010). Conversely, others actively endorse the term disability as it creates a sense of community across the survivor/service user/mad and disability movements (Price, 2013). Yet, others are reluctant to use “disability” for the fear of being accused that they are not disabled enough; that they do not have the appropriate life-long impairments (Spandler and Anderson, 2015, 24). The reluctance of some within the Mad movement to accept the social model of disability and adopt its terminology has been interpreted by a physically disabled activist as reflecting the “disablism” prevalent within sections of this movement (Withers, 2014). That is, in refusing to be referred to as disabled and in asserting that unlike disabled people they have no tangible, “real” impairment, these activists are contributing to the idea that disability is a fixed thing and not an outcome of the interaction between individual capacities and specific social/physical contexts. Fear of increased stigma is another stumbling block for a shared discourse and activities between the disability and the Mad movements. Each group faces its own distinctive stigma in society, and to take on the term “madness” or the term “disability” is to take on an extra challenge (Withers, 2014).
Although these are important issues, the key point for the argument here is the underlying framework and not the terminology in place: what is of essence in the medical/social model framework is an account of the interaction between the individual and society in relation to the production of limitations on everyday activity. With regard to naming, one may eschew the problematic term “impairment” for the less-loaded one “variation,” and one need not use the word “disability” at all. On the question of what constitutes a mental variation we don’t need to assume some account of natural function by which mental functions (and variations thereof) can be specified—the idea of natural function has already been problematised.15 Given the argument presented earlier, a relevant mental variation is one that is made salient when our complex activity in the world is disrupted. It would not be “schizophrenia” or “psychosis,” but the features that typically underlie these diagnoses such as voices, paranoid beliefs, anxious feelings, difficulties understanding social behavior, mood fluctuations, impaired attention and concentration, and others. These features can impose a range of limitations on the ability of individuals to realize their goals and to participate in everyday social situations and interactions. A few examples will illustrate:
A person who experiences chronic anxiety (or paranoia) finds it difficult to negotiate the long, crowded, bright lanes of the local mall and heads home without shopping. We can look at this disruption to activity from two vantage points: as a problem with the world or as a problem with one’s mental state (anxiety). Wherever we start, the other vantage point is implied: the difficulty of negotiating the mall makes salient my anxious feelings; my anxious feelings make salient the difficulty of negotiating the mall.
A person hears voices and converses with them, as she finds this helpful and affords her a measure of control. When she does this in public people give her strange looks and sometimes walk away from her. Due to this, on many days she feels unable to leave the house and her social isolation is increasing. Here, as with the previous example, the disruption to activity (social isolation) can be seen as a consequence of one’s behavior or due to negative social responses, with each view made salient by the other.
A person experiences fluctuations in mood; when “high” he can work for many hours on end, frequently overnight. Such episodes are followed by several days of rest during which he feels tired and low in mood. Due to this, he is unable to keep consistent employment as his line of work cannot accommodate the requirement for erratic working hours. In this case, disruption to activity (employment) can be seen as a consequence of his mood fluctuations or due to unaccommodating working arrangements.
In each case, once a specific mental variation is identified, it becomes possible to reflect on the variation/environment mismatch and to formulate more precisely what exactly needs to change: modify the mental state/behavior, alter the environment, or some combination of the two.
The issues are different when the variation in question consists in a strongly held, nonconsensual belief: a “delusion.” For the sake of exposition consider two paradigmatic examples: the belief that one is persecuted by certain agents (persecutory delusion) and the belief that one’s spouse has been replaced by an impostor (Capgras delusion). On the basis of such beliefs, the person holding them may, respectively, barricade himself at home or avoid the spouse.16 For an outside observer who can see that both beliefs are false, those individuals are subjecting themselves to unnecessary limitations; they are disabled by their beliefs. But for the believers themselves, this insight would not arise as long as they continue to hold the requisite belief with conviction.17 For them, the problems they experience are facts about the world—that one is unsafe and that one’s spouse is an impostor—and not the beliefs per se. In terms of the basic idea underlying the social model, as argued in Section IV, what is made salient by what appears to be disruption to daily activity is not one’s mental state, but facts about the social world. If I refuse to leave the house because someone is waiting outside for me with a gun, I am not disabled; I am sensible. If I am convinced that I am under threat despite there being no threat, then others may consider me disabled by my belief, but I would not. In this specific respect, “delusional” beliefs are outside the scope of the social model. They are brought back within it, however, in a different manner.
The “delusional” person may experience limitations of a different sort. He or she may experience discrimination, disqualification, and ridicule for the very fact of holding the belief(s) in question. In this respect, the discrimination in question would be no different to that which some religious minorities or sects face, except in relation to the question of numbers; the delusional person goes it alone, whereas sects tend to have a larger following. Here, we are brought back within the scope of the social model, as I am prevented from accessing the same rights and respect as other citizens due to the beliefs that I hold. A remedy could be to change the belief or, alternatively, to change the social environment by making it more accepting and tolerant.18
The earlier examples show that even though the issues are complex and will require conceptual work and ingenuity, it is possible to apply social model thinking to at least some mental variations and related behaviors. In fact, this approach to mental variations has made its way to a number of publications by academics, policy makers, and charities in the United Kingdom and elsewhere.19 These publications have issued recommendations on reasonable adjustments in the work place for people with “mental disabilities.” Underlying this is the understanding that by contrast to physical impairments, mental variations tend to be less visible, have a more significant impact on the social rather than the built environment, and hence will require adjustments that focus on social interactions and relationships (Department for Work and Pensions, 2009). Among the recommendations: time-out if one feels anxious or paranoid, flexible hours, reduced workload, quieter workspace, private rather than open-plan working arrangements, availability of contact with a support worker or friend if someone feels particularly paranoid, working conditions matched to a person’s tolerance for contact with large numbers of people, and combating stigma among colleagues at work. The mental health charity Rethink Mental Illness (2012, 9) goes further, stating that stigma and negative attitudes of colleagues “can undermine adjustments that would otherwise be effective.”
Rethink is exactly right to point toward stigma as a major issue: without some significant change in how people think about madness/mental health problems, any proposed adjustments will be superficial and of limited effectiveness. Further, stigma and negative perceptions may impact on individuals’ self-esteem and psychological and emotional well-being, thus creating further barriers to participation.20 Yet in pushing to alter such attitudes, the Department for Work and Pensions (2009) and Rethink Mental Illness (2012) advance or support the line of thought that mental health problems are illnesses akin to physical illnesses, in the sense that they occur for reasons outside a person’s control (which arguably reduces blame), can be treated, are not to be feared, and are not a sign of weakness. However, as an anti-stigma strategy, this is problematic on two counts: first, studies have shown that the argument that “mental illness is an illness like any other” does not reduce stigma, in fact it is associated with perceptions of unpredictability, dangerousness, and fear (Read et al. 2006); second, this argument is antithetical to the demand for recognition of madness as an identity, where concerned groups do not see themselves as ill and where aspects of madness are reformulated in a positive light or, at least, neutrally. Rethink is correct in pointing out that negative attitudes can genuinely hamper a person’s ability to partake in the work environment; the difficult question is to specify what lies at the root of the problem in society at large.
To put this differently, impaired concentration, anxiety, paranoia, and social withdrawal are experiences that are commonplace enough not to generate any severe or unique discrimination from others. Most people are familiar with these experiences—think of sleep deprivation, jet lag, or a bad hangover—and readily find excuses for each other for them and, if they are generous, accommodate each other for them. What generates particular challenges in the case of madness is precisely the association of such experiences with phenomena that generate fear and distrust in others. To be anxious or paranoid due to the effects of alcohol overuse is not the same as having those experiences due to hearing voices or harboring fears that one is persecuted by government agencies or by invisible beings. The latter are phenomena that, for most people, defy simple, if any, meaningful explanation and from there engender a certain kind of disqualification and possibly distrust grounded in the apparent unintelligibility of these phenomena. At the point where this occurs, it is hard to sustain a social interaction in which the unique variations and traits of a person are noted and respected in order to create for him or her a more accommodating environment. More likely than not, when unintelligibility sets in we move from a position of accommodation to one of seeing the person before us as the main cause of their struggles. Intelligibility, therefore, is an important idea and merits a further look.
VI. Intelligibility and the Limits of Social Accommodation
There is no doubt that the variations discussed in Section V differ in significant respects when compared with mobility and sensory variations in relation to the question of social accommodation. One difference, noted by Pilgrim and Tomasini (2012, 634), is that at the heart of the social reaction to “mental health problems” is an “attributed loss or lack of reason.” By contrast, with mobility and sensory variations (physical disability more broadly), that capacity is not at stake. Assumed lack of reason, they continue, underpins the disadvantage and discrimination that characterize the social response to madness; it underpins fear and distrust as well as paternalistic limitations of autonomy. Unreason here is used quite broadly and ranges from not being able to meet social obligations (due to anxiety or depression) to failures in intelligibility exemplified by individuals whose behavior is underpinned by voices, bizarre delusions, thought disorder, or other states that for some may resist everyday understanding.21 Intelligibility emerges as a helpful concept in marking out more precisely an important, if not central, factor that determines the limits of social accommodation of difference: the point at which we cease to consider discourses of social adjustment in favor of those that describe, in various ways, some sort of failure in the individual, for example, that he or she is “mentally ill.”
Consider the experience of hearing voices and its impact on behavior. A “voice-hearer” (Woods, 2013) may at times converse with the voices and be distracted by them. In some social contexts, as indicated earlier, behaving in this way can generate negative responses from others that may lead the voice-hearer into isolation and fears of appearing in public. In this example, developing social narratives in which voice hearing is normalized or marked out as a unique experience can engender a measure of intelligibility and tolerance of the associated behaviors, and this in turn may improve social inclusion for the voice-hearer. As Spandler and Anderson (2015, 19) note, this is what the Hearing Voices Movement has been seeking to do: to affect a shift from the view of voices as symptoms of illness to that of voices as meaningful phenomena. Intelligibility will depend on the kind of narrative put forward to create this meaningfulness. Some narratives draw connections between voice hearing, spirituality, and nonhuman agents such as spirits. Others see voices as denoting aspects of self and hence as offering a means for a more profound understanding of one’s past and identity.
For the voice-hearer’s interlocutor, intelligibility will depend on the extent to which he or she is able to accept the assumptions supporting the different narratives. And, herein lies the challenge of expanding our limits of the social accommodation of difference and our ability to conceive social adjustments: madness asks us to question our total worldview; to question our beliefs, values, sense of self, ideas of rationality, and personhood.22 The change required here is not to install a ramp or an alternate sign, it is to change notions fundamental to us as persons and to broaden the idea of what is possible. This is most evident in cross-cultural encounters. Consider, for example, a person who barricades himself at home on hearing the voice of a spirit threatening him with death if he leaves his house. Whether we consider this an “illness”—after all it appears to be a paradigmatic example of “action failure”—or a genuine threat, will depend on the extent to which we take the cause of the obstruction as real.23 In cultural contexts where spirits are considered to exist and to have a say in human affairs, that person’s self-imposed incarceration may appear to others as a sensible course of action until the spirit is dealt with. In cultural contexts where the “spirit” is understood as alienated mental content—objectified aspects of self—that person may be considered “ill. ”
While we are on the theme of cross-cultural encounters, we can consider other phenomena that appear to really defy intelligibility across cultural contexts. Such phenomena, thought disorder, for example, do not enjoy the “collective reasonableness” and positive reframing achieved by, say, the Hearing Voices Movement (Pilgrim and Tomasini, 2012, 642; Spandler and Anderson, 2015, 18–9). Jones and Kelly (2015, 47), mental health activists and academics, assert that “the struggles of a distressed individual who can nevertheless communicate with others, can and must be distinguished from an individual with thought disorder so severe that he or she can no longer be understood, even in the most basic of ways.” For Jones and Kelly, the limit of intelligibility is thought disorder, which is the limit it would appear of thought itself. For other less accommodating individuals, the limit lies much earlier, being evident for them in the slightest eccentricity in belief or behavior. The limit of intelligibility lies at different places for different people and, as indicated previously, marks out the point at which we begin to consider the limitations experienced by an individual to flow from the variation itself. At this point, we cease to consider changing social behavior in favor of changing the individual.
There are two bulwarks against this move or, at least, against assuming it too readily. The first has already been mentioned earlier and concerns the need to specify the values and standards by which one was driven to regard a particular variation as intrinsically disabling. In doing so, one may give more thought to the possibility of changing those standards in a way that would permit a broader accommodation of difference. The second bulwark arises from political activism: from the very demand for social justice raised by activists.
VII. Political Activism and the Social Subject
Mad Pride activists demand change in the social beliefs, norms, values, and overall practices that define madness/mental illness—essentially society’s total understanding and treatment of these “conditions.” The expectation is for society to change to accommodate a unique identity or culture. Hence, a major site of change is the reductive, discriminatory, and disrespectful language that dominates public and professional narratives, a language in which key terms all indicate deficit and pathology: disease, illness, disorder, delusion, hallucination, and, of course, “madness” itself before its reclamation by activists. In this respect, Mad Pride’s demands lie on a par with demands for recognition long voiced by the more familiar collective identities constructed around race, gender, and sexuality. Indeed, as indicated at the outset, the analogy with Gay and Black rights is central to the discourse and is frequently pointed out. In urging cultural change, the demands of Mad Pride go beyond the equalization of civil rights irrespective of difference (which requires a politics of equality that rejects discrimination on the basis of morally irrelevant features) but, rather, the recognition of that difference as a matter of social justice: the distinctness of the identity in question, its claim to respect and equality.
The demand that society should change to accommodate a broader range of variations as a matter of justice implies that the person making this demand is a social subject. What is meant by “social subject” will shortly become apparent, but as an approximation it can be taken to mean a human being who sees oneself and sees others as engaged in a shared project in which each individual’s well-being is at stake and equally matters. Now at first sight, this claim may appear paradoxical, for a popular view in both lay and scholarly accounts is that a central aspect of madness (or of “schizophrenia”) is the dis-sociality of the subject; a sign of mad subjects’ madness is their withdrawal from society. For example, a person with severe paranoia may have a radical, sometimes global, loss of interpersonal trust; for that person, others appear not as co-participants in a shared project but as a threat to one’s existence. In a related manner, the phenomenological psychopathology literature describes the “schizophrenic” person as having a crisis of intersubjectivity; a disruption to the two fundamental poles of social reality: sensus communis and attunement.24 Other times the “schizophrenic” person is described as having a disorder of consciousness and self-awareness; an ipseity disturbance characterized by hyperreflexivity and diminished self-affection (this view also concerns the “schizophrenic” person’s dis-sociality but starts from subjectivity rather than intersubjectivity).25 These accounts may seem to invalidate the idea that the “schizophrenic” person can be a social subject in the sense described earlier. If one accepts this conclusion, how do we make sense of those making the demand for social justice? One (cynical) approach is to claim that Mad Pride activists are not really mad at all. Another approach is to argue that the issue here is a matter of scope: the phenomena referred to by phenomenological psychopathology are at the far-end of the spectrum of sociality and are not representative of all “schizophrenic,” “psychotic” or mad experiences.26 I reject the first approach and accept a qualified version of the second, as will be evident in what follows. But first, I return to the idea of the social subject implied by the demands of activists.
Implied by the demand for the accommodation of a broader range of variations as a matter of justice are, at least, the following:
An understanding of oneself as an individual among others.
An understanding that individuals are different in some respects from each other, i.e., human diversity.
An understanding that individual well-being depends, in part, on the sustenance provided by social interactions and arrangements.
The ability to see oneself as part of a smaller group that is part of wider society.
An understanding of oneself as a person who possesses rights and whose claims merit recognition.
An understanding that others too possess rights (this is already implied by the way in which the demand is couched in the language of justice and fairness).
In short, what is implied by the demand is a view on social justice and an understanding of society. Returning to the limits of intelligibility discussed in Section VI, we can say that by virtue of making this demand—notwithstanding the unintelligibility of specific experiences or behaviors—the person should be seen as a candidate for the social accommodation of difference rather than the medical (individual) correction (treatment) of behavior; the demand should act as a bulwark against the prioritization of an individual approach. The reason this is so is that the demand trumps the objection against social accommodation. In the terms raised here, this objection can be put as follows: mad individuals are, as it were, outside society, and to argue for accommodating their behaviors and mental variations is to risk losing society altogether, grounded as it is in shared rules and assumptions. The political demand demonstrates the person’s sociality and appreciation of the shared meta-project that is society, and hence refutes this objection.
Returning to the point I made earlier concerning the scope of sociality, it is true that some mad (or “schizophrenic”) experiences appear incompatible with sociality, a point made in phenomenological psychopathology. However, I see those whom phenomenological psychopathology describes as suffering with a crisis in intersubjectivity to be those subjects who are yet to see their situation in terms of identity, diversity, and social justice; who are yet to be brought to a conception of themselves as social subjects. Here, the principle of consciousness-raising that is described in the activist literature is instructive. This is the process by which people get together, share stories, see similarities in their situations, and interpret their predicaments as arising from discriminatory and difficult social conditions rather than individual pathology. Once this is achieved, a demand is made to change those conditions. Given this, an actual key goal within activist communities is to support individuals such that they are able to make that demand. In this endeavor, creating “collective reasonableness” in relation to particular phenomena is also crucial. It may not be possible for some individuals to make the demand despite such support, and for others they may not wish to make it, opting instead for a more individual, illness-based discourse and intervention. But by redescribing the problem of sociality as a problem to be partly worked out in activism and political action, we are able to erect a bulwark against the tendency to see it in terms of disorder and individual pathology.
VIII. Conclusion
Along the decades, different groups have campaigned and struggled for respect and rights; some have been successful at achieving symbolic and cultural reparation, others less so. The enlarged scope of Gay rights in parts of North Europe, North America, and a few select other regions is usually cited as a success story. It is now pointed out that societies need to come to terms with the rights of transgender individuals and the respect they may be owed. Yet, Mad individuals, and madness more broadly, are yet to feature in the conversation on respect and identity, a conversation still dominated by framings that emphasize the medical idiom and the notions of distress and disability. This paper sought to address the problem of disability by erecting two bulwarks against the tendency to assume, too readily, a medical interpretation of the limitations experienced by individuals with the kind of variations in mental function that fall under the umbrella term “madness.”
The first bulwark arose from an analysis of the disability model that revealed the normative basis of disability judgments: when we say that a variation (or impairment) is intrinsically disabling we need to accompany this judgment with an account of the values, norms, abilities, and contexts that underpin it. This requirement, though it may appear too subtle to make a difference, actually brings about a profound change in perspective: instead of seeing the limit of our ability to understand and accommodate difference as an indication of a (natural) problem with the difference itself, we come to view it as a normative limit constituted by values, norms, and abilities that go so deep they appear natural. With this insight in place, it becomes possible to resist medicalizing difference, and reflect on what possible social solutions can be put in place to accommodate it.
The second bulwark arose from reflection on the implications of political activism. To demand, as a matter of social justice, that society changes to accommodate a broader range of variations in function is to be a social subject; it is to be a candidate for the accommodation of difference rather than the individual (medical) correction of behavior.
There is no question that effecting the recommended change in perspective is a challenging endeavor. Although applying social model thinking to mental variations (to madness) is possible—as I have demonstrated—it raises issues different from the kind of variations in physical function for which the social model of disability was initially developed. A key difference is the way in which madness presents a challenge of intelligibility; it asks us to question and broaden our values and beliefs with respect to fundamental notions such as our sense of self and overall worldview. Difficult though as that may be, at least we can now come to view this (apparently) insurmountable difference for what it is: as a radical challenge to norms and concepts constitutive of who we are. Whether we should attempt, as a matter of moral obligation, to change these norms and concepts in order to accommodate a broader range of experiences and behaviors is a further question to be considered.
Footnotes
This paper is based on a larger research project in Rashed (Forthcoming). Parts of this paper will appear in the book.
For accounts of Mad Pride written by activists consult Curtis et al. (2000), Costa (2015), Sen (2011), Triest (2012), deBie (2013), and Smiles (2011). See also Asylum Magazine (UK), Spring 2011, Mad Pride issue, Volume 18, No. 1. For records, flyers and announcements of past, recent and upcoming Mad Pride events consult the following websites: Hamilton: [http://madpridehamilton.ca/]; Toronto: [https://madprideto2015.wordpress.com/]; Liverpool: [http://www.liverpoolmentalhealth.org/mad-pride/]; International: [http://www.mindfreedom.org/campaign/madpride/events]. See also: Mad Pride issues of the Consumer/Survivor Resource Centre of Canada Bulletin (online: http://www.csinfo.ca/bulletin.php). Note that Mad Pride is capitalized to denote a group identity much like Gay Pride, for example. All links functional on July 19, 2018.
See DuBrul (2014), and the ICARUS project website, online: https://theicarusproject.net/mission-vision-principles/
Elsewhere, I have explored, with Rachel Bingham, some of the issues raised by the concept of distress in relation to the distinction between “social deviance” and “mental disorder” (Rashed and Bingham, 2014).
The term “well-being” is used here in a colloquial, non-technical sense.6.See, for example, the UK Equality Act (2010), the US Americans with Disabilities Act (1990), and the United Nations Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities (2006)
See Silvers (2010) for a good philosophical overview of the social model of disability.
Note the difference between a person born with a sensory inability—blindness, for example—and a person who loses sight as an adult. The latter experiences a radical change in functional capacities that may be very distressing and disabling and may take some time to adapt to. On the other hand, a person born blind may not necessarily experience blindness as a salient obstacle in everyday life. This may change, however, if that person wishes, for example, to seek employment or further his or her independence. At that point, not being able to see in the context of a physical environment that does not take this particular sensory inability into account, may generate disability.
It is possible for a particular state to become salient without resulting in disruption to daily activity; a twisted ankle may cause pain and discomfort without rendering the sufferer immobile. Similarly, one may experience sadness, paranoia, or anxiety without this limiting social interaction or activity. However, the discussion in this section concerns disability, and the issue is disruption to activity.
A possible objection to this point is that a person with paraplegia and no recourse to a wheelchair may find it very difficult to move from point A to point B. Here, he is clearly thwarted in realizing his goal and the obstruction is not a consequence of unaccommodating social arrangements. However, disability theorists who endorse the social model for mobility impairments begin their argument by assuming the presence of a wheelchair. Disability consists in the limitations faced by the wheelchair user in environments with limited stair-free access. Critics could object that you cannot assume the wheelchair as it is not part of a human’s natural embodiment. Once you remove the wheelchair, they could argue, the extent of non-socially imposed disability becomes evident. A response to this objection is to think of the wheelchair as a tool that improves the functional abilities of persons who cannot walk. If I come across a 1-ton boulder and find myself unable to push it out of my path, I face a limit to my functional capacities, but I do not thus conclude that there is a disorder with my abilities (unless I am Hercules). To move the boulder, I make use of tools either to break it down to smaller parts or to somehow push it out of the way. Human beings use tools throughout the day to help them compensate for their functional capacities and accomplish tasks that otherwise would not be possible. The wheelchair is a tool in this sense, and it is acceptable to assume it as a given in arguments concerning the social basis of disability.
Note that the focus here is on the generation of disadvantage (limitation) and not on the factors implicated in the genesis of the variation/impairment in the first place, which can include various psychological, biological and social factors.
Unconditional disadvantages are referred to in the disability literature as “impairment effects.” These include the discomfort, pain, and inabilities, which disabled people face and are distinguished in the literature from the disadvantages experienced as a consequence of social restrictions and discrimination (Thomas, 2004).
Reference classes are included by Boorse to account for the wide variation of function within Homo sapiens: normal function in a newborn would not be the same as an 8-year-old child.
There are many critiques of naturalist accounts of (dys)function; the following are particularly helpful: Boorse (2011, 26–37) for a summary of the theories and the objections; Bolton (2008) presents a short critique of Boorse’s theory and a substantial analysis and critique of Wakefield’s; Kingma (2013) contains an overview of both theories and a general critique of naturalist accounts of disorder.
There have been some recent calls to adopt the discourse of “neurodiversity” as a positive replacement for the language of “impairment” (Graby, 2015; see also McWade et al., 2015). Advocates of this move believe that this would bring about a positive change: instead of “impairments” we would have a diversity of “minority neurotypes” that stand alongside so-called “normal neurotypes” as real and valid neurological types. These neurotypes, it is argued, should be accommodated as an element of diversity such as race or ethnicity. A major problem with the neurodiversity discourse is that it assumes that existing categories and identities (e.g., Autism, Attention Deficit Hyperactivity Disorder, Normal, and Mad) can be traced back to a shared “neurology.” But, our identifications and categorizations of behavior—as is now generally accepted in the domain of mental health—do not “cut nature at the joints” or reflect natural discontinuities. If so, then there is not much sense in the claim that there are distinct neurological types essentially different from each other. Further, neurodiversity raises a number of difficult questions; for example: what exactly is a “normal” neurotype? Do all “normals” share one neurotype? Do all people with “autism” share one neurotype? Neurodiversity may be important from an activism point of view, but as an argument it does not work.
Not all “deluded” individuals act on their beliefs, a phenomenon known as double bookkeeping (see
Sass and Pienkos, 2013, 646–50). An oft used example is that of the man locked in an asylum who believes he is Napoleon yet does nothing toward exercising his regal powers.
This can change if the person develops primary insight into the delusional nature of the belief; if he or she is able to see that it is false, that he is not persecuted and that her husband is not an impostor. In such cases the person loses conviction in the belief and is able to see that it really was determining behavior in limiting ways.
Making society more tolerant is a solution that tends to be pursued in communities that advance notions of free speech and multicultural acceptance. The flip side of this tolerance is for the groups in question to develop secondary insight (a point which also applies to the “delusional” person). Secondary insight refers to subjects’ abilities to see their beliefs from the point of view of common social values and norms, and in doing so to see that others may find those beliefs unusual or bizarre. The benefit of secondary insight is that it introduces appreciation of what others’ views are without requiring agreement with those views. It allows contrasting beliefs to exist side by side, with both groups remaining aware that it will be difficult to reconcile those beliefs with each other. This is to be contrasted with primary insight, which as a notion in psychiatric practice refers to the person conceding the falsity of her (delusional) beliefs and demonstrating awareness that she is “ill.”
See Heron and Greenberg (2013), Thornicroft et al (2008), Goering (2009), the UK Department for Work and Pensions (2009), and the mental health charity Rethink (2012). Of note is that the UK Department of Health now recognizes as a disability a mental health condition that lasts more than 12 months and affects normal day-to-day activity. Among the listed conditions that may lead to disability are schizophrenia, depression, and bipolar disorder. By being classified a disability, a mental health condition falls under the protection of the Equality Act (2010) and the United Nations Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities (2006). According to these acts, the state is under an obligation to provide individuals with disabilities the chance to participate fully in all aspects of life through provision of reasonable adjustments that promote access to and engagement with the environment.
This is referred to in the disability literature as psycho-emotional disablism (see Reeves, 2015).
In each of these cases intelligibility means something different. With voices, the issue may be that such experiences are completely alien given my worldview. With bizarre delusions, I may be struck by how patently false these claims are or fail to understand why this person is holding them. With thought disorder, there may be a more basic inability to grasp any meaning at all in what a person is saying. The point here, however, is not to parse out the different forms of failure of understanding (see Rashed, 2015), or to suggest ways of enlarging intelligibility.
In contrast, mobility and sensory impairments ask us, primarily, to question our embodiment. I say primarily because many physical conditions also generate huge stigma— human immunodeficiency virus (HIV), for example, or leprosy—and hence also implicate the self of patient and other.
It would constitute action failure in so far as it is a negatively evaluated experience of incapacity, where incapacity is defined as a failure of intentional action (Jackson and Fulford, 1997, 54). The example provided fulfils the two requisite elements for action failure: (1) there is a failure of intentional action (the person is unable to make his will effective and not due to an external cause). (2) This incapacity is negatively evaluated. (See also Rashed, 2010, 189–90.)
This account is found in a number of works, particularly the work of Giovanni Stanghellini (2004).
This account is found in the work of Louis Sass, Joseph Parnas, and others (see Parnas and Handest, 2003; Sass, 2003; Sass and Parnas, 2007)
A third approach is to cast doubt on the methodology by which the conclusions of phenomenological psychopathology are reached (see Rashed, 2015).
References
Allan, C 2006. Misplaced pride. The Guardian  [On-line]. Available: http://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2006/sep/27/society.socialcare (accessed July 6, 2018).
Amundson, R 1992. Disability, handicap, and the environment. Journal of Social Philosophy  23(1):105–19.
———. 2000. Against normal function. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Science  31(1):33–53.
Amundson, R and Tresky, S 2007. On a bioethical challenge to disability rights. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy  32(6):541–61.
Beresford, P 2000. What have madness and psychiatric system survivors got to do with disability and disability studies? Disability and Society  15(1):167–72.
———. 2005. Social approaches to madness and distress: User perspectives and user knowledge. In Social Perspectives in Mental Health: Developing Social Models to Understand and Work with Mental Distress , ed. JTew, 32–52, London, United Kingdom: Jessica Kingsley Publishers.
Beresford, P, M. Nettle, and R. Perring. 2010. Towards a social model of madness and distress: Exploring what service users say. Joseph Rowntree Foundation  [On-line]. Available: https://www.jrf.org.uk/sites/default/files/jrf/migrated/files/mental-health-service-models-full.pdf (accessed July 6, 2018). 
deBie, A 2013. And what is Mad Pride? Opening speech of the First Mad Pride Hamilton Event on July 27, 2013. This Insane Life  1:7–8.
Bolton, D. 2008. What is Mental Disorder? An Essay in Philosophy, Science and Values . Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
———. 2013. What is mental illness. In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Psychiatry, eds. K. W. MFulford, M Davies, R Gipps, G Graham, J Sadler, G Stanghellini, and T Thornton, 434–50. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
Boorse, C 1997. A rebuttal on health. In What is Disease? , eds. JHumber and RAlmeder, 1–134. Totowa, NJ: Humana Press.
———. 2011. Concepts of health and disease. In Philosophy of Medicine , ed. FGifford, 13–64. Amsterdam, The Netherlands: Elsevier.
Costa, L 2015. Mad Pride in our mad culture. Consumer/Survivor Information Resource Centre Bulletin  [On-line]. Available: http://www.csinfo.ca/bulletin/Bulletin_535.pdf (accessed July 6, 2018).
Curtis, T, RDellar, ELeslie, and B Watson, eds. 2000. Mad Pride: A Celebration of Mad Culture . Truro, United Kingdom: Chipmunkapublishing.
Department for Work and Pensions. 2009. Realising Ambitions: Better Employment Support for People with a Mental Health Condition . London, United Kingdom: The Stationery Office Limited.
DuBrul, S 2014. The Icarus Project: A counter narrative for psychic diversity. Journal of Medical Humanities  35(3):257–71.
Goering, S 2009. “Mental illness” and justice as recognition. Philosophy and Public Policy Quarterly  29(1/2):14–8.
Graby, S 2015. Neurodiversity: Bridging the gap between the Disabled People’s Movement and the Mental Health System Survivors’ Movement. In Madness, Distress and the Politics of Disablement , eds. HSpandler, J Anderson, and BSapey 231–44. Bristol, United Kingdom: Policy Press.
Heron, R, and N. Greenberg. 2013. Mental health and psychiatric disorders. In Fitness for Work: Medical Aspects, eds. KPalmer, I Brown, and JHobson, 132–54. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
Jackson, M and K. Fulford. 1997. Spiritual experience and psychopathology. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology  4(1):41–65.
Jones, N, and T. Kelly. 2015. Inconvenient complications: On the heterogeneities of madness and their relationship to disability. In Madness, Distress and the Politics of Disablement , eds. HSpandler, JAnderson, and BSapey, 43–56. Bristol, United Kingdom: Policy Press.
Jost, A 2009. Mad Pride and the medical model. Hastings Centre Report  39(4):c3.
Kingma, E 2007. What is it to be healthy? Analysis  67(294):128–33.
———. 2013. Naturalist accounts of mental disorder. In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Psychiatry, eds. K. W. MFulford, MDavies, RGipps, GGraham, JSadler, GStanghellini, and TThornton, 363–84. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
McWade, B, D. Milton, and P. Beresford. 2015. Mad Studies and neurodiversity: A dialogue. Disability and Society  30(2):305–09.
Mulvany, J 2000. Disability, impairment or illness? The relevance of the social model of disability to the study of mental disorder. Sociology of Health and Illness  22(5):582–601.
Nordenfelt, L 1997. The importance of a disability/handicap distinction. The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy  22(6):607–22.
Oliver, M 1990. The Politics of Disablement . Basingstoke, United Kingdom: Macmillan.
———. 1996. Understanding Disability . Basingstoke, United Kigndom: Macmillan.
———. 2004. The social model in action: If I had a hammer. In Implementing the Social Model of Disability: Theory and Research , eds. CBarnes and GMercer, 18–31. Leeds, United Kingdom: Disability Press.
Parnas, J, and P. Handest. 2003. Phenomenology of anomalous self-experience in early schizophrenia. Comprehensive Psychiatry  44(2):121–34.
Perring, C 2009. “Madness” and “brain disorders”: Stigma and language. In Configuring Madness: Representation, Context and Meaning , ed. KWhite, 3–24. Oxford, United Kingdom: Inter-Disciplinary Press.
Pilgrim, D, and F. Tomasini. 2012. On being unreasonable in modern society: Are mental health problems special? Disability and Society  27(5):631–46.
Polvora, 2011. Diagnosis “human”. Icarus Project Zine  [On-line]. Available: http://legacy.theicarusproject.net/content/essay-persuasive-diagnosis-human-polvora (accessed on July 6, 2018).
Price, M 2013. Defining mental disability. In The Disability Studies Reader, ed. LDavis, 298–307. New York: Taylor & Francis.
Rashed, M. A 2010. Religious experience and psychiatry: Analysis of the conflict and proposal for a way forward. Philosophy, Psychiatry & Psychology  17(3):185–204.
———. 2015. A critical perspective on second-order empathy in understanding psychopathology: Phenomenology and ethics. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics  36(2):97–116.
———. Forthcoming. Madness & the Demand for Recognition: A Philosophical Inquiry into Identity & Mental Health Activism. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
Rashed, M. A, and R. Bingham. 2014. Can psychiatry distinguish social deviance from mental disorder? Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology  21(3):243–55.
Read, J, N. Haslam, L. Sayce, and E. Davies. 2006. Prejudice and schizophrenia: A review of the ‘mental illness is an illness like any other’ approach. Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavia  114(5):303–18.
Reeves, D 2015. Psycho-emotional disablism in the lives of people experiencing mental distress. In Madness, Distress and the Politics of Disablement , eds. HSpandler, JAnderson, and BSapey, 99–112. Bristol, United Kingdom: Policy Press.
Rethink Mental Illness. 2012. What’s Reasonable at Work? A Guide to Rights at Work for People with a Mental Illness  [On-line]. Available: https://moodle.adaptland.it/pluginfile.php/20622/mod_data/content/54370/Whats%20reasonable%20at%20work.pdf (accessed July 6, 2018).
Sass, L 2003. Self-disturbance in schizophrenia: Hyperreflexivity and diminished self-affection. In The Self in Neuroscience and Psychiatry, eds. TKircher and ADavid 242–71. Cambridge, United Kigndom: Cambridge University Press.
Sass, L and J. Parnas. 2007. Explaining schizophrenia: The relevance of phenomenology. In Reconceiving Schizophrenia, eds. MChung, K. W. MFulford, and GGraham, 63–96. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
Sass, L, and E. Pienkos. 2013. Delusion: The phenomenological approach. In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Psychiatry, eds. K. W. MFulford, MDavies, RGipps, GGraham, JSadler, GStanghellini, and TThornton, 632–57. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press
Sen, D 2011. What is Mad Culture? Asylum: The Magazine for Democratic Psychiatry 18(1):5.
Silvers, A 2010. An essay on modeling: The social model of disability. In Philosophical Reflections on Disability, eds. DRalston and JHo, 19–36. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer
Smiles, S 2011. Indicator species. Icarus Project Zine  [On-line]. Available: http://nycicarus.org/images/waxandfeathers.pdf (accessed July 6, 2018).
Spandler, H and J. Anderson. 2015. Unreasonable adjustments? Applying disability policy to madness and distress. In Madness, Distress and the Politics of Disablement , eds. HSpandler, JAnderson, and BSapey, 13–25. Bristol, United Kingdom: Policy Press.
Stanghellini, G 2004. Disembodied Spirits and Deanimated Bodies: The Psychopathology of Common Sense . Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
Terzi, L 2004. The social model of disability: A philosophical critique. Journal of Applied Philosophy  21(2):141–57.
Thomas, C 2004. Developing the social relational in the social model of disability: A theoretical agenda. In Implementing the Social Model of Disability: Theory and Research, eds. CBarnes and GMercer, 32–47. Leeds, United Kingdom: Disability Press.
Thornicroft, G, E. Brohan, A. Kassam, and E. Lewis-Holmes. 2008. Reducing stigma and discrimination: Candidate interventions. International Journal of Mental Health Systems  2(3):1–7.
Triest, A 2012. Mad? There’s a movement for that. Shameless Magazine  21:20–1.
United Kingdom Parliament. 2010. Equality Act 2010 [On-line] Available: https://www.legislation.gov.uk/ukpga/2010/15/pdfs/ukpga_20100015_en.pdf (accessed August 13, 2018).
United Nations. 2006. Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities [On-line]. Available: https://www.un.org/development/desa/disabilities/convention-on-the-rights-of-persons-with-disabilities.html (accessed August 13, 2018).
United States Congress. 1990. Americans with Disabilities Act of 1990 [On-line]. Available: https://www.ada.gov/archive/adastat91.htm (accessed August 13, 2018).
Wakefield, J 1992. The concept of mental disorder: On the boundary between biological facts and social values. American Psychologist  47(3):373–88.
Withers, A 2014. Disability, divisions, definitions, and disablism: When resisting psychiatry is oppressive. In Psychiatry Disrupted: Theorizing Resistance and Crafting the (R)evolution , eds. BBurstow, BLeFrancois, and SDiamond 114–28. Montreal, Canada: Mc-Gill-Queen’s University Press.
Woods, A 2013. The voice-hearer. Journal of Mental Health  22(3):263–70.
2 notes · View notes
leadgen · 7 years
Text
What Are the Advantages of Hiring an Emergency Plumber in Central Coast
Emergency plumber Central Coast is someone whom you can immediately call for help in a plumbing emergency. When you have a plumbing emergency, you will most likely be confused and distressed. The last thing you will want to do is contact various plumbers and have to compare the different services and options available to you. Most probably, you will not have adequate time to consider the options available to you as you will require a plumber urgently. Therefore, it is vital that you do your research before you face any urgent situation so that you are able to find the right plumbers who offer a 24 hour service and are experienced plumbers for all plumbing problems.
Emergency Plumber Central Coast must be Qualified and Experienced.
When emergency plumber Central Coast receives a call from you, they will determine your problem over the phone and will send the most qualified personnel to you. An emergency plumber needs to be very skilled and must be able to perform any type of plumbing job successfully. In order to work in an emergency situation, the emergency plumber Central Coast will send a qualified plumber with a van which is fully equipped with a wide range of tools and materials suitable for any sort of plumbing work. You must be confident that once you have put your faith in the hands of an emergency plumber Central Coast, you will not be let down or disappointed.
Emergency Plumber Central Coast must be Available Any Time.
Usually when you require the service of a plumber after hours, most emergency plumbing services will charge a higher rate for the job. The reason being that the plumbers pay rates for afterhours work is much higher than normal rates.   You need to be sure that the service which you are going to receive is affordable to you. If you think that a company will provide you with a superior service, but its rate is a bit high, then you have to make your own decision which must take into account how quickly a plumber will attend to the job and know the quality of his service. After hours plumbing is also suitable for those individuals who go to their workplace daily and work from nine to five. If the regular plumbing service hours happen to clash with your day job, then it will be extremely difficult for you to call a plumber during normal hours unless you have a friendly and trustworthy relationship with a regular plumber and you are happy to give him access to your home during normal hours without you being present. A plumbing problem can interrupt your daily routine so you should ensure that you are able to minimize this interruption. You can trust the emergency plumber Central Coast to accomplish the job perfectly at any time of the day or night.
Get to Know Your Emergency Plumber Central Coast Before you have a Plumbing Emergency.
Some of the plumbing problems like a burst pipe or a leaking roof need to be solved immediately. If these issues are not taken care of in proper time, they might cause serious damage which will be expensive and time-consuming to fix. These types of problems can cause serious hazards to your home’s structural integrity. In such cases, the emergency plumber Central Coast must assist you to attend to a crises situation promptly.
Therefore, the best advice is to develop a relationship with your Local Plumber Central Coast so that you know you have a competent and trustworthy Plumber Central Coast whenever you require his services.
Local Plumber Central Coast is your local plumber Central Coast specialist. If you have an issue with a blocked drain Central Coast or hot water system Central Coast, then you need a 24 hour plumber Central Coast or an emergency plumber Central Coast to service you. You might also reach out to a gas plumber Central Coast to help you. It’s important that you have a plumber Central Coast, Central Coast plumber, plumbing Central Coast, plumbers Central Coast you can trust. Drain Camera Central Coast and Carbon Monoxide Testing Central Coast are other service we offer to our clients. Emergency Plumbing Central Coast is important to your home system. Do you have a Burst Pipe Central Coast? Make sure to visit our contact page.
We service many suburbs including: Plumber Buff Point, Plumber Bushells Ridge, Plumber Calga, Plumber Canton Beach, Plumber Cedar Brush Creek, Plumber Budgewoi Peninsula, Plumber Budgewoi, Plumber Bouddi, Plumber Booker Bay, Plumber Blue Haven, Plumber Blue Bay, Plumber Blackwall, Plumber Berkeley Vale, Plumber Bensville, Plumber Bateau Bay, Plumber Bar Point, Plumber Ettalong Beach, Plumber Erina Heights, Plumber Erina, Plumber Empire Bay, Plumber East Gosford, Plumber Durren Durren, Plumber Doyalson, Plumber Dooralang, Plumber Davistown, Plumber Wyong, Plumber Wyoming, Plumber Woy Woy Bay, Plumber West Gosford, Plumber Wamberal, Plumber Tumbi Umbi, Plumber Tuggerah, Plumber Toowoon Bay, Plumber The Entrance, Plumber Terrigal, Plumber Tascott, Plumber Tacoma, Plumber Springfield, Plumber Somersby, Plumber Shelly Beach, Plumber Saratoga, Plumber Point Frederick, Plumber Point Clare, Plumber Picketts Valley, Plumber Peats Ridge, Plumber Palmdale, Plumber Palm Grove, Plumber Ourimbah, Plumber North Gosford, Plumber North Avoca, Plumber Niagara Park, Plumber Narara, Plumber Mount Elliot, Plumber Matcham, Plumber Mardi, Plumber Long Jetty, Plumber Lisarow, Plumber Kincumber, Plumber Killarney Vale, Plumber Kiar, Plumber Kariong, Plumber Kanwal, Plumber Kangy Angy, Plumber Jilliby, Plumber Holgate, Plumber Hamlyn Terrace, Plumber Halloran, Plumber Halekulani, Plumber Green Point, Plumber Gosford, Plumber Gorokan, Plumber Glenworth Valley, Plumber Glenning Valley, Plumber Fountaindale, Plumber Forresters Beach
0 notes
oldmotors · 4 years
Photo
Tumblr media
It was October, 1968 when GM Chairman Jim Roche announced that GM would finally build a proper American small car. The car Roche had in mind was in its early stages - GM’s XP-887, a corporate project under Ed Cole and Clare MacKichan and not yet a Chevrolet - but in less than two years, it would arrive as the Chevrolet Vega. The infamously rushed development and internal conflicts eventually resulted in lots of bad PR for the car and GM. Today’s subject, though, is a curious aside in Vega’s history and about its prowess as a performance platform. The Vega came in four distinct models - three of which were not at all surprising - the two-door sedan, the hatchback coupe, and the kammback wagon. The fourth, however, was a commercial vehicle - the Vega Panel Express. Sedan Deliveries were basically over in the U.S. after 1962 and Chevrolet had built its last in 1960. Their place had been taken by light vans and pickups, but in other countries “van” sedans (Citroën GS, Morris Marina, Corolla) were still common. By blanking out the glass on the Kammback wagon and putting in a stripped interior, Chevy hoped to lure in U.S. buyers who might still want such a van - handymen, painters, plumbers. The Panel had just one seat standard, though many were ordered with a passenger seat. Naturally it was a bantamweight. What Chevy found was that their instincts in dropping sedan deliveries had been correct. The Panel’s best year was its first, 1971, with ~8,700 sold, falling to about half that in 1972/3/4, and just over 1,500 in 1975, at which point the Panel was dropped. Although new customers didn’t appreciate the Panel, hot rodders and customizers did. It was easy to drop a V8 into a Vega, a phenomenon that had already begun even before the debut of the Cosworth Vega or Vega-derived V8 Monza. A V8 gave the Vega serious speed (and better reliability) and the Panel, often with 70s-era custom van graphics applied, became a desirable item for drag racers. This early Vega Panel (not an original but a scan from the OM archives) is pictured in late 1970s L.A. sporting several hot rod club stickers, though the engine is unknown. The majority of surviving panels are hot rods today. (at Glendale, California) https://www.instagram.com/p/B8zBBkAFrmO/?igshid=1frzh827mxrcu
0 notes
Text
Vancouver library story hour celebrates diversity, playfulness
Find out how to get the best plumber in Vancouver Washington
Apparently, children and their parents can go enjoy a different sort of storytime at the Vancouver Community Library on Feb. 9. This one will be rainbow-colored, all-inclusive, costume-positive and simply fabulous.
If your notion of storytime leadership is a mousy librarian intoning something tranquil, like “Goodnight Moon,” take another look.
The Feb. 9 reader will be a Portland nightclub star who hails from Vancouver. Her stage name is Clare Apparently, and she’ll be decked out in full drag. The event is called Drag Queen Story Hour.
“We haven’t settled on the books yet,” Apparently said, “but they’ll probably be about diversity and acceptance and friendship across differences. We’re working off lists that were compiled by the national organization with the help of professional children’s librarians.”
That national organization, launched in 2015 in San Francisco, has now spread Drag Queen Story Hours to many libraries across the nation — including Portland and even Longview.
Vancouver library officials call Drag Queen Story Hour an effort to reach out and make marginalized people in our community feel safe and welcome. It’s a way to teach tolerance, teach self-acceptance and prevent bullying, they said.
“As an organization, we feel it’s an important part of our mission to look at equity, diversity and inclusion,” said Amelia Shelley, executive director of the Fort Vancouver Regional Libraries system. “We want to normalize the message that everybody is different.”
That’s the same message the library tries for with its materials collection and its other programs, from English as a Second Language to computer-coding classes, staff development coordinator Blake Kincaid added: responding to community needs and representing diverse points of view. Drag Queen Story Hour “is just an extension of what we do with our collection,” Kincaid said.
But here’s one key difference: officials said no taxpayer dollars will be spent on the event, which is supported entirely by funds from the independent Friends of the Vancouver Community Library group. Not tapping public money for a happening that some people find objectionable was a careful decision, Kincaid said.
“This is not a regular storytime, which we have all the time,” Kincaid said. “This is a special event and we’ll evaluate it afterwards. It’s not for every single family, but for families who feel a need and choose to attend.”
Visible, optional
Because it’s historically been an “invisible need,” Shelley added, our whole culture is climbing a learning curve about gender identity and fluidity now. New visibility provokes “deep-seated feelings people have about gender identity,” she said. “It’s certainly generated more interesting comments than I would have expected.”
On Facebook, those comments range from “Yay!” to “Disgusting.”
“This atrocity has already spread like a plague to libraries throughout the Portland area,” one commentor wrote. “This must not be tolerated!”
Heidi St. John, a Christian motivational speaker based in Vancouver, hinted at a live protest: “Are you ready to get off the bench? The fact that this is being pushed on our kids is a tragedy, and it will not stop until people are willing to stand up to this wicked agenda!”
“Have sign, will travel,” another commentor responded.
Families first
Because space is limited and the event is intended for children and families who will appreciate it, priority admittance will be given to families with children, according to senior public services librarian Kari Kunst.
The library is not pushing anything at anyone, public services director Amy Lee emphasized, just meeting existing community needs. “All public libraries try to cover community needs. We are giving this one a try,” she said.
Unlike public schools, Shelley said, the library’s mission is to provide for everyone, but not parent anyone. When it comes to attending events, borrowing materials and exposing children to new ideas, she said, “We expect parents and caregivers to make those choices.”
Another Facebook commenter said: “In the words of my 9 year old, if you don’t like it, don’t go. But don’t be rude.”
Not a nightclub act
Clare Apparently grew up as Kit Crosland, a Vancouver native who attended Evergreen High School.
“I know from talking to some of the teachers as an adult, it was in their contract that they would lose their employment if they ever told a student they were gay” (until such discrimination was banned), she said.
“That’s how, on the institutional level, we limit role models for LGBTQ children and teenagers. That’s the sort of lack that could have been filled in by community and library events. I would have appreciated it so much when I was a child.”
Apparently said Vancouver’s Drag Queen Storytime will be completely age-appropriate — not a racy nightclub act. Apparently granted that some online objections “aren’t completely baseless,” because the nighttime drag world is “very adult-focused. It’s all about adult things, and that’s great in the right environment.”
But Apparently, who has worked with youth at social service nonprofits and elementary schools, said Drag Queen Storytime will be nothing but child-oriented. “I know how to hang out with kids. I know how to make the transition from 21-and-up drag queen to child appropriate,” she said.
“A large part of my drag is about playfulness,” Apparently said. “I always think of recapturing the energy of being 5 years old, turning on a radio and dancing in the living room in front of the mirror. The freedom and joy of loving that song, loving yourself, dancing in your body, letting it all out. That’s the direction I take my drag — recapturing the joy of childhood that’s been pressured out of us.”
IF YOU GO
What: Drag Queen Story Hour.
When: 2:30 to 3:30 p.m. Feb. 9.
Where: Vancouver Community Library, 901 C St.
Admission: Free. Priority admission for families with children.
[Read More …]
Find out how to get the best Vancouver Washington plumber
0 notes
prokred · 7 years
Text
What's making you happy? Kind <b>plumbers</b>, homecomings and Santa
Our lovely plumber moving his appointments around to come fix our heating this morning #IrishTimesHappy. — Clare Kavanagh (@kavanagh_clare) December 11, 2017. After weeks and weeks on tenterhooks regarding his visa, our son Brian finally confirmed he's coming home from Canada for ... Read more http://ift.tt/2AvZReY Areas served: Winston-Salem, High Point, Yadkinville, Mocksville, Advance, Clemmons, Kernersville, Greensboro, Walnut Cove, Statesville, NC, North Carolina Services: House painting, roofing, deck building, landscaping, Carpentry, Flooring, tile, hardwood, remodeling, home improvement, interior, exterior
0 notes
leadgen · 7 years
Text
24 Hour Plumber Central Coast – It pays to hire an experienced Plumber
Getting the right 24 Hour Plumber Central Coast to offer you emergency services may not be as simple as it appears. In hiring a 24 Hour Plumber Central Coast, you must be sure they have the experience and carry spare parts in order to do the repairs . This is the reason why Local Plumber Central Coast is the best and quickest 24 Hour Plumber Central Coast which will offer the best services.
Why 24 Hour Plumber Central Coast is the best:
Reputation and experience
The reputation and experience of our technician are crucial. You should  not get influenced by some of the adverts and idle promises of inexperienced plumbers . Reliable facts concerning our company can be obtained from references from our many clients. Their experience will tell you how 24 Hour Plumber Central Coast services are the best.
24 Hour Plumber Central Coast is licensed
You can be assured that our technicians you hire have the vital skills to perform any plumbing task. Our 24 Hour Plumber Central Coast services are performed by licensed plumbers who have the knowledge and experience to perform all task promptly and cost effectively.
We offer 24 Hour Plumbing services
We offer plumbing services at any time as we operate on a twenty-four-hour daily basis. This is to cover for emergency calls at night. Reliability is essential in an emergency plumbing situation. When you make an urgent call at night, we will attend to the situation promptly and not wait until the next day. This will prevent further damage to your property.
24 Hour Plumber Central Coast has qualified personnel
Our professional plumbers are well trained to deal with any plumbing situation that may arise day or night. All our qualified plumbers must have their trade licenses before our company will consider employing them. This ensures that from us you only get the services of qualified and knowledgeable plumbing technician.  
Below we have listed some of the plumbing services that a 24 Hour Plumber Central Coast can offer.
These services require expertise and skills in identifying problems and providing reliable solutions. From maintaining systems, doing repairs and making installations, plumbing services are of great value to all commercial and residential building owners.
Residential plumbing services
Residential plumbing services are one of the most sought-after services especially in homes. Some of the common problems that occur are leaking or cracked pipes, backed up sewer systems, drain clogs, slow flowing drains, burst pipes, water supply problems, toilet clogs and others.
Maintenance and repair
Maintenance and repair of installations and systems is a crucial service. By doing this, you ensure that all the systems are in good state and working correctly. Servicing is provided for installations such as toilets, bathtubs, drain pipes, kitchen sinks, faucets, sewer lines, garbage disposals, water softeners, hot water systems, gas meters etc.
Commercial plumbing services
24 Hour Plumber Central Coast provides commercial plumbing services to business owners. Systems and equipment used in commercial buildings are often complicated and require specialized skills to service. Advanced technology such as video camera inspection of water and sewer pipes is used. 24 Hour Plumber Central Coast services also cover any plumbing emergencies required by clients.
Specialized drain and sewer cleaning services
24 Hour Plumber Central Coast professionals provide specialized drain and sewer cleaning services. Sewer and drain systems often need frequent maintenance to ensure they are working appropriately. Specialized services include repairing floor drain issues, pipe repairs, removal of dirt and tree roots inside drain pipes and septic system cleaning.
Plumbing systems inspection
Plumbing inspection of systems is another common service provided by 24 Hour Plumber Central Coast. Inspection helps assess the condition of all installed systems, look for potential problems, identify them and provide necessary advice on repairs needed. The value of these services is very crucial for anyone who owns a residential or commercial building.
In summary, Local Plumber Central Coast is the best company when it comes to offering plumbing services. Give us a call, and we will be ready to solve your problem.
Local Plumber Central Coast is your local plumber Central Coast specialist. If you have an issue with a blocked drain Central Coast or hot water system Central Coast, then you need a 24 hour plumber Central Coast or an emergency plumber Central Coast to service you. You might also reach out to a gas plumber Central Coast to help you. It’s important that you have a plumber Central Coast, Central Coast plumber, plumbing Central Coast, plumbers Central Coast you can trust. Drain Camera Central Coast and Carbon Monoxide Testing Central Coast are other service we offer to our clients. Emergency Plumbing Central Coast is important to your home system. Do you have a Burst Pipe Central Coast? Make sure to visit our contact page.
We service many suburbs including: Plumber Buff Point, Plumber Bushells Ridge, Plumber Calga, Plumber Canton Beach, Plumber Cedar Brush Creek, Plumber Budgewoi Peninsula, Plumber Budgewoi, Plumber Bouddi, Plumber Booker Bay, Plumber Blue Haven, Plumber Blue Bay, Plumber Blackwall, Plumber Berkeley Vale, Plumber Bensville, Plumber Bateau Bay, Plumber Bar Point, Plumber Ettalong Beach, Plumber Erina Heights, Plumber Erina, Plumber Empire Bay, Plumber East Gosford, Plumber Durren Durren, Plumber Doyalson, Plumber Dooralang, Plumber Davistown, Plumber Wyong, Plumber Wyoming, Plumber Woy Woy Bay, Plumber West Gosford, Plumber Wamberal, Plumber Tumbi Umbi, Plumber Tuggerah, Plumber Toowoon Bay, Plumber The Entrance, Plumber Terrigal, Plumber Tascott, Plumber Tacoma, Plumber Springfield, Plumber Somersby, Plumber Shelly Beach, Plumber Saratoga, Plumber Point Frederick, Plumber Point Clare, Plumber Picketts Valley, Plumber Peats Ridge, Plumber Palmdale, Plumber Palm Grove, Plumber Ourimbah, Plumber North Gosford, Plumber North Avoca, Plumber Niagara Park, Plumber Narara, Plumber Mount Elliot, Plumber Matcham, Plumber Mardi, Plumber Long Jetty, Plumber Lisarow, Plumber Kincumber, Plumber Killarney Vale, Plumber Kiar, Plumber Kariong, Plumber Kanwal, Plumber Kangy Angy, Plumber Jilliby, Plumber Holgate, Plumber Hamlyn Terrace, Plumber Halloran, Plumber Halekulani, Plumber Green Point, Plumber Gosford, Plumber Gorokan, Plumber Glenworth Valley, Plumber Glenning Valley, Plumber Fountaindale, Plumber Forresters Beach
0 notes
leadgen · 7 years
Link
We service many suburbs including: Plumber Buff Point, Plumber Bushells Ridge, Plumber Calga, Plumber Canton Beach, Plumber Cedar Brush Creek, Plumber Budgewoi Peninsula, Plumber Budgewoi, Plumber Bouddi, Plumber Booker Bay, Plumber Blue Haven, Plumber Blue Bay, Plumber Blackwall, Plumber Berkeley Vale, Plumber Bensville, Plumber Bateau Bay, Plumber Bar Point, Plumber Ettalong Beach, Plumber Erina Heights, Plumber Erina, Plumber Empire Bay, Plumber East Gosford, Plumber Durren Durren, Plumber Doyalson, Plumber Dooralang, Plumber Davistown, Plumber Wyong, Plumber Wyoming, Plumber Woy Woy Bay, Plumber West Gosford, Plumber Wamberal, Plumber Tumbi Umbi, Plumber Tuggerah, Plumber Toowoon Bay, Plumber The Entrance, Plumber Terrigal, Plumber Tascott, Plumber Tacoma, Plumber Springfield, Plumber Somersby, Plumber Shelly Beach, Plumber Saratoga, Plumber Point Frederick, Plumber Point Clare, Plumber Picketts Valley, Plumber Peats Ridge, Plumber Palmdale, Plumber Palm Grove, Plumber Ourimbah, Plumber North Gosford, Plumber North Avoca, Plumber Niagara Park, Plumber Narara, Plumber Mount Elliot, Plumber Matcham, Plumber Mardi, Plumber Long Jetty, Plumber Lisarow, Plumber Kincumber, Plumber Killarney Vale, Plumber Kiar, Plumber Kariong, Plumber Kanwal, Plumber Kangy Angy, Plumber Jilliby, Plumber Holgate, Plumber Hamlyn Terrace, Plumber Halloran, Plumber Halekulani, Plumber Green Point, Plumber Gosford, Plumber Gorokan, Plumber Glenworth Valley, Plumber Glenning Valley, Plumber Fountaindale, Plumber Forresters Beach
Local Plumber Central Coast is your local plumber Central Coast specialist. If you have an issue with a blocked drain Central Coast or hot water system Central Coast, then you need a 24 hour plumber Central Coast or an emergency plumber Central Coast to service you. You might also reach out to a gas plumber Central Coast to help you. It’s important that you have a plumber Central Coast, Central Coast plumber, plumbing Central Coast, plumbers Central Coast you can trust. Drain Camera Central Coast and Carbon Monoxide Testing Central Coast are other service we offer to our clients. Emergency Plumbing Central Coast is important to your home system. Do you have a Burst Pipe Central Coast? Make sure to visit our contact page.
0 notes
leadgen · 7 years
Text
Central Coast Plumber: 24*7 Plumbing Solutions
We often take our water service for granted until we need the help of a Central Coast Plumber. Clogged drains, garbage disposals, and backed-up toilets are just a few of the common plumbing problems that can be solved by Local Plumber Central Coast.
It is important to ensure that you choose your Central Coast plumber before experiencing any form of emergency so that you can be sure of making the right choice. Most people however usually wait until they need plumbing help before they choose a plumber. It is however not easy to put trust in someone especially if you do not have an idea whether they are the right person for the job. This is why one requires a few guidelines that are going to help them choose Local Plumber Central Coast. They offer fast, efficient repairs and replacements for the following problems:
1-Central Coast Plumber Can Repair Blocked Drains
Don't let a clogged drain put your day on hold. A plumbing service such as Local Plumber Central Coast can unclog your kitchen sink, bathtub or blocked toilet. Your Central Coast plumber will clear the pipes beneath your sinks or flush the sewer drain if a clogged toilet is backing up into your shower or tub.
2- Central Coast Plumber Can Repair a Faulty Toilet
A toilet that overflows or doesn't flush properly is one of the most frustrating household problems you can encounter. Quite often the issue can be remedied by replacing or repairing a part inside the toilet tank. If the bowl is leaking, it may be a supply line problem. If water is leaking from underneath the toilet bowl, Local Plumber Central Coast will reseal it. If that doesn't work, it may be a blockage in the waste line which they can then fix.
3- Central Coast Plumber Can install or Repair a Hot Water System
When you turn on the shower and get sprayed with a cold water even when you've turned the valve to hot, contact Central Coast Plumber to check the Hot Water System. If you hear a popping sound from your gas heater or there's a rotten egg smell coming from it, there may be sediment at the bottom of the tank. A Local Plumber Central Coast can fix these issues by flushing the tank. If your water Hot Water System is more than ten years old or has a leak, your best option is to have a Central Coast Plumber replace it for you.
4- Central Coast Plumber Can Assist with Remodelling Your Home
If you're remodelling your home, a Central Coast Plumber will work with you to add a bathroom, half-bathroom or laundry room. A certified plumber can hook-up dishwashers and sinks in your kitchen, install showers, hot tubs, appliances or supply gas to pool heaters. Your Local Plumber Central Coast has energy-efficient faucets and toilets that will save water, energy and meet local environmental standards.
5-Central Coast Plumber Can Repair Water Leaks
Leaky faucets waste up to 10,000 gallons of water in the average household every year. An experienced Central Coast Plumber can replace valve seals or washers to stop leaks and prevent further waste. Getting to the bottom of a difficult leak may entail cutting a hole in a wall to check pipes and pipe fittings. Your Central Coast Plumber will need to replace deteriorated pipes to stop serious leaks.
Local Plumber Central Coast is your local plumber Central Coast specialist. If you have an issue with a blocked drain Central Coast or hot water system Central Coast, then you need a 24 hour plumber Central Coast or an emergency plumber Central Coast to service you. You might also reach out to a gas plumber Central Coast to help you. It’s important that you have a plumber Central Coast, Central Coast plumber, plumbing Central Coast, plumbers Central Coast you can trust. Drain Camera Central Coast and Carbon Monoxide Testing Central Coast are other service we offer to our clients. Emergency Plumbing Central Coast is important to your home system. Do you have a Burst Pipe Central Coast? Make sure to visit our contact page.
We service many suburbs including: Plumber Buff Point, Plumber Bushells Ridge, Plumber Calga, Plumber Canton Beach, Plumber Cedar Brush Creek, Plumber Budgewoi Peninsula, Plumber Budgewoi, Plumber Bouddi, Plumber Booker Bay, Plumber Blue Haven, Plumber Blue Bay, Plumber Blackwall, Plumber Berkeley Vale, Plumber Bensville, Plumber Bateau Bay, Plumber Bar Point, Plumber Ettalong Beach, Plumber Erina Heights, Plumber Erina, Plumber Empire Bay, Plumber East Gosford, Plumber Durren Durren, Plumber Doyalson, Plumber Dooralang, Plumber Davistown, Plumber Wyong, Plumber Wyoming, Plumber Woy Woy Bay, Plumber West Gosford, Plumber Wamberal, Plumber Tumbi Umbi, Plumber Tuggerah, Plumber Toowoon Bay, Plumber The Entrance, Plumber Terrigal, Plumber Tascott, Plumber Tacoma, Plumber Springfield, Plumber Somersby, Plumber Shelly Beach, Plumber Saratoga, Plumber Point Frederick, Plumber Point Clare, Plumber Picketts Valley, Plumber Peats Ridge
0 notes
leadgen · 7 years
Link
We service many suburbs including: Plumber Buff Point, Plumber Bushells Ridge, Plumber Calga, Plumber Canton Beach, Plumber Cedar Brush Creek, Plumber Budgewoi Peninsula, Plumber Budgewoi, Plumber Bouddi, Plumber Booker Bay, Plumber Blue Haven, Plumber Blue Bay, Plumber Blackwall, Plumber Berkeley Vale, Plumber Bensville, Plumber Bateau Bay, Plumber Bar Point, Plumber Ettalong Beach, Plumber Erina Heights, Plumber Erina, Plumber Empire Bay, Plumber East Gosford, Plumber Durren Durren, Plumber Doyalson, Plumber Dooralang, Plumber Davistown, Plumber Wyong, Plumber Wyoming, Plumber Woy Woy Bay, Plumber West Gosford, Plumber Wamberal, Plumber Tumbi Umbi, Plumber Tuggerah, Plumber Toowoon Bay, Plumber The Entrance, Plumber Terrigal, Plumber Tascott, Plumber Tacoma, Plumber Springfield, Plumber Somersby, Plumber Shelly Beach, Plumber Saratoga, Plumber Point Frederick, Plumber Point Clare, Plumber Picketts Valley, Plumber Peats Ridge, Plumber Palmdale, Plumber Palm Grove, Plumber Ourimbah, Plumber North Gosford, Plumber North Avoca, Plumber Niagara Park, Plumber Narara, Plumber Mount Elliot, Plumber Matcham, Plumber Mardi, Plumber Long Jetty, Plumber Lisarow, Plumber Kincumber, Plumber Killarney Vale, Plumber Kiar, Plumber Kariong, Plumber Kanwal, Plumber Kangy Angy, Plumber Jilliby, Plumber Holgate
Local Plumber Central Coast is your local plumber Central Coast specialist. If you have an issue with a blocked drain Central Coast or hot water system Central Coast, then you need a 24 hour plumber Central Coast or an emergency plumber Central Coast to service you. You might also reach out to a gas plumber Central Coast to help you. It’s important that you have a plumber Central Coast, Central Coast plumber, plumbing Central Coast, plumbers Central Coast you can trust. Drain Camera Central Coast and Carbon Monoxide Testing Central Coast are other service we offer to our clients. Emergency Plumbing Central Coast is important to your home system. Do you have a Burst Pipe Central Coast? Make sure to visit our contact page.
0 notes
leadgen · 7 years
Text
Do You Have Problems with your Hot Water System Central Coast?
Plumber Tumbi Umbi, Hot Water System Central Coast can cause problems every once in awhile.
Sometimes, when you turn on the shower, it takes a while for the water to heat up. This is due to the amount of distance between the hot water system Central Coast and faucet. This may explain why when you hop into the shower, you are overcome with a cold blast of water! A solution to this is to have a small, water heater in your bathroom.
Another issue that occurs with a hot water system Adelaide is low water pressure.
Your hot water pipes are most likely clogged up with deposited minerals. This can cause you water pressure to go from a great amount of pressure with cold water, to barely any water coming out of the faucet with hot water! If you do not want this to occur, you can call a plumber Central Coast to flush out your water heater yearly and clean out your pipes.
Another problem with hot water system Central Coast is that the water temperature drops.
If you have several people in your home, this is a common problem. After some people take nice, hot showers, they leave you with the icy, cold water that nobody wants! We all know that that's not very fun! A solution to this issue is having your local plumber Central Coast come and either install a larger water tank heater, or install a tankless water heater. This way, the entire family can enjoy nice, warm showers!
You may also wonder why your hot water system Central Coast is noisy.
Well, the answer to this is that residue builds up in your hot water system Central Coast, and this may cause those loud pops and pings you hear every now and then! The residue building up in your hot water system can take up a lot of space in your tank, leaving you with a reduced water volume. If this is an issue for you, you can call your plumber Central Coast to flush out and drain the tank.
Another possible trouble you may have is that your hot water system  Central Coast smells.
No one wants their house filled with an unpleasant odor! You may have this problem because bacteria is entering through your pipes and is growing. Yuck! Luckily, you can call a plumber Central Coast to handle this issue for you.
If you are experiencing any of these problems with your hot water system Central Coast, other problems, or just want a new hot water system Central Coast installed, you can call a plumber Central Coast to fix them. This way, all your hot water problems will be gone!
We service many suburbs including: Plumber Buff Point, Plumber Bushells Ridge, Plumber Calga, Plumber Canton Beach, Plumber Cedar Brush Creek, Plumber Budgewoi Peninsula, Plumber Budgewoi, Plumber Bouddi, Plumber Booker Bay, Plumber Blue Haven, Plumber Blue Bay, Plumber Blackwall, Plumber Berkeley Vale, Plumber Bensville, Plumber Bateau Bay, Plumber Bar Point, Plumber Ettalong Beach, Plumber Erina Heights, Plumber Erina, Plumber Empire Bay, Plumber East Gosford, Plumber Durren Durren, Plumber Doyalson, Plumber Dooralang, Plumber Davistown, Plumber Wyong, Plumber Wyoming, Plumber Woy Woy Bay, Plumber West Gosford, Plumber Wamberal, Plumber Tumbi Umbi, Plumber Tuggerah, Plumber Toowoon Bay, Plumber The Entrance, Plumber Terrigal, Plumber Tascott, Plumber Tacoma, Plumber Springfield, Plumber Somersby, Plumber Shelly Beach, Plumber Saratoga, Plumber Point Frederick, Plumber Point Clare, Plumber Picketts Valley, Plumber Peats Ridge, Plumber Palmdale, Plumber Palm Grove, Plumber Ourimbah, Plumber North Gosford, Plumber North Avoca, Plumber Niagara Park, Plumber Narara, Plumber Mount Elliot, Plumber Matcham, Plumber Mardi, Plumber Long Jetty, Plumber Lisarow, Plumber Kincumber, Plumber Killarney Vale, Plumber Kiar, Plumber Kariong, Plumber Kanwal, Plumber Kangy Angy, Plumber Jilliby, Plumber Holgate
Local Plumber Central Coast is your local plumber Central Coast specialist. If you have an issue with a blocked drain Central Coast or hot water system Central Coast, then you need a 24 hour plumber Central Coast or an emergency plumber Central Coast to service you. You might also reach out to a gas plumber Central Coast to help you. It’s important that you have a plumber Central Coast, Central Coast plumber, plumbing Central Coast, plumbers Central Coast you can trust. Drain Camera Central Coast and Carbon Monoxide Testing Central Coast are other service we offer to our clients. Emergency Plumbing Central Coast is important to your home system. Do you have a Burst Pipe Central Coast? Make sure to visit our contact page.
0 notes
leadgen · 7 years
Link
We service many suburbs including: Plumber Buff Point, Plumber Bushells Ridge, Plumber Calga, Plumber Canton Beach, Plumber Cedar Brush Creek, Plumber Budgewoi Peninsula, Plumber Budgewoi, Plumber Bouddi, Plumber Booker Bay, Plumber Blue Haven, Plumber Blue Bay, Plumber Blackwall, Plumber Berkeley Vale, Plumber Bensville, Plumber Bateau Bay, Plumber Bar Point, Plumber Ettalong Beach, Plumber Erina Heights, Plumber Erina, Plumber Empire Bay, Plumber East Gosford, Plumber Durren Durren, Plumber Doyalson, Plumber Dooralang, Plumber Davistown, Plumber Wyong, Plumber Wyoming, Plumber Woy Woy Bay, Plumber West Gosford, Plumber Wamberal, Plumber Tumbi Umbi, Plumber Tuggerah, Plumber Toowoon Bay, Plumber The Entrance, Plumber Terrigal, Plumber Tascott, Plumber Tacoma, Plumber Springfield, Plumber Somersby, Plumber Shelly Beach, Plumber Saratoga, Plumber Point Frederick, Plumber Point Clare, Plumber Picketts Valley, Plumber Peats Ridge
Local Plumber Central Coast is your local plumber Central Coast specialist. If you have an issue with a blocked drain Central Coast or hot water system Central Coast, then you need a 24 hour plumber Central Coast or an emergency plumber Central Coast to service you. You might also reach out to a gas plumber Central Coast to help you. It’s important that you have a plumber Central Coast, Central Coast plumber, plumbing Central Coast, plumbers Central Coast you can trust. Drain Camera Central Coast and Carbon Monoxide Testing Central Coast are other service we offer to our clients. Emergency Plumbing Central Coast is important to your home system. Do you have a Burst Pipe Central Coast? Make sure to visit our contact page.
0 notes
leadgen · 7 years
Text
Reasons You'll Need a Plumber to Unclog Your Blocked Drain Central Coast
Blocked drain Central Coast are a great help when it comes to tackling problems at home by many families. Unwanted annoyance is caused due to blockage in kitchen sinks, toilet drains, shower cables, faucets and various other drains. Such blockages result in waste water logging and foul odor countenance which create further inconvenience to the people facing it. Some of the reasons you'll need a plumber to unclog your blocked drain Central Coast are:
Blocked drain Central Coast provides effective solution
Blocked drain Central Coast service, however, provides a better and effective solution to the issues relating to blocked drains. They have especially skilled plumbers who make the use of advanced equipment to disentangle the hindrances like tree roots, hair locks and certain other waste that affect the smooth and proper working of drains and pipes. Thus, they help in releasing the flow of choked water.
Use of advanced equipment in Blocked Drain Central Coast
More equipped machines and techniques like CCTV drain cameras are installed in blocked drains as a part of blockage clearance solution. Such cameras enable the plumber to find out the exact location of the accumulated waste choked in the pipes and drains and also traces out if there are any cracks or further obstacles in the flow of the water. Thus, the implementation of this technique restores the proper flow of water.
Blocked drain Central Coast offer 24 hour service
There is an easy accessibility to the Blocked drain Central Coast service since it works 24/7. Thus it proves to be quick and functional every time, and hence one can rely on this service to maintain one's plumbing and drainage system. The service not only unblocks the choked and blocked drains but also furnishes one with minimum resources and educates people in DO-IT-YOURSELF techniques in case of extreme emergency.
Internment of drain acid is yet another proficient method employed by this service to set free the block drains and pipes. This drain acid is extremely operative since it is a huge potential drain acid which burns through the waste clogged in the drain without really damaging the drain or pipe. Thus, it ensures the guarantee of work done.
Blocked drain Central Coast experts offer full responsibility
Blocked drain Central Coast provides the customer with dexterous commercial plumbers to offer best plumbing services in Central Coast. Once the drain specialist inspects and diagnoses the blocked drain, he makes it sure that the problem is attended properly and within an hour the issue proves to be solved. This service not only proves to be time-effective but it is also economical and reliable.
Unlike some plumbers throughout Central Coast, our technicians don't believe that any mess or debris left behind after clearing the blockage is your responsibility. Blocked drain Central Coast plumbers ensure that the area of operation is left every bit clean as it was when they walked in. If you're not 100% satisfied with the service you receive from Blocked drain Central Coast, they'll return to the site to rectify any issues free of charge.
Every one of their plumbers is trade qualified and holds a valid plumbing licence and every case is treated with same professionalism whether it's domestic, commercial or industrial. Unblocking drains is one of the most frequent things handled by the Blocked drain Central Coast company and they've developed incredibly efficient processes to ensure the problems are dealt with quickly.
Local Plumber Central Coast is your local plumber Central Coast specialist. If you have an issue with a blocked drain Central Coast or hot water system Central Coast, then you need a 24 hour plumber Central Coast or an emergency plumber Central Coast to service you. You might also reach out to a gas plumber Central Coast to help you. It’s important that you have a plumber Central Coast, Central Coast plumber, plumbing Central Coast, plumbers Central Coast you can trust. Drain Camera Central Coast and Carbon Monoxide Testing Central Coast are other service we offer to our clients. Emergency Plumbing Central Coast is important to your home system. Do you have a Burst Pipe Central Coast? Make sure to visit our contact page.
We service many suburbs including: Plumber Buff Point, Plumber Bushells Ridge, Plumber Calga, Plumber Canton Beach, Plumber Cedar Brush Creek, Plumber Budgewoi Peninsula, Plumber Budgewoi, Plumber Bouddi, Plumber Booker Bay, Plumber Blue Haven, Plumber Blue Bay, Plumber Blackwall, Plumber Berkeley Vale, Plumber Bensville, Plumber Bateau Bay, Plumber Bar Point, Plumber Ettalong Beach, Plumber Erina Heights, Plumber Erina, Plumber Empire Bay, Plumber East Gosford, Plumber Durren Durren, Plumber Doyalson, Plumber Dooralang, Plumber Davistown, Plumber Wyong, Plumber Wyoming, Plumber Woy Woy Bay, Plumber West Gosford, Plumber Wamberal, Plumber Tumbi Umbi, Plumber Tuggerah, Plumber Toowoon Bay, Plumber The Entrance, Plumber Terrigal, Plumber Tascott, Plumber Tacoma, Plumber Springfield, Plumber Somersby, Plumber Shelly Beach, Plumber Saratoga, Plumber Point Frederick, Plumber Point Clare, Plumber Picketts Valley, Plumber Peats Ridge
0 notes
bluewatsons · 5 years
Text
Mohammed Abouelleil Rashed, In Defense of Madness: The Problem of Disability, 44 J Med & Phil (2019)
Abstract
At a time when different groups in society are achieving notable gains in respect and rights, activists in mental health and proponents of mad positive approaches, such as Mad Pride, are coming up against considerable challenges. A particular issue is the commonly held view that madness is inherently disabling and cannot form the grounds for identity or culture. This paper responds to the challenge by developing two bulwarks against the tendency to assume too readily the view that madness is inherently disabling: the first arises from the normative nature of disability judgments, and the second arises from the implications of political activism in terms of being a social subject. In the process of arguing for these two bulwarks, the paper explores the basic structure of the social model of disability in the context of debates on naturalism and normativism, the applicability of the social model to madness, and the difference between physical and mental disabilities in terms of the unintelligibility often attributed to the latter.
I. Introduction
For a number of decades, there have been considerable attempts to develop positive narratives of mental health phenomena, narratives that can counter- act the pervasive, negative views in society and the profession of psychiatry.1 The context in which these attempts were and are made is a burgeoning movement(s) of activism and advocacy in mental health. A recent chapter in this activism is Mad Pride, a movement and discourse that pose a direct and radical challenge to the social norms and values underpinning views on “mental illness.”2 Mad Pride discourse rejects the language of “illness” and “disorder,” reclaims the term “mad,” and replaces its negative connotations with more positive understandings. It reverses the customary understand- ing of madness as illness in favor of the view that madness can be grounds for identity and culture. In addition, Mad positive approaches and framings abound in the writings of activists: phenomena of madness such as states of heightened sensory awareness, visions and voices, and the ability to perceive complexity and significance in everyday experiences are considered special and valuable, and not indicators of psychopathology. Their value is sometimes taken to arise from the creative, artistic, cultural, and spiritual potential afforded by these experiences.
Mad Pride discourse recognizes that madness can also be associated with distress and difficulties in social functioning. This Janus-faced nature of mad- ness—at once a source of creativity and suffering—led to the formulation that individual traits and sensitivities are “dangerous gifts” that require cultivation and care.3 Yet, it is the question of distress and disability that has proved to be a sticking point for Mad Pride discourse and for mad positive approaches in general: how can one advance a positive framing of that which appears to be inherently negative? This criticism has been expressed strongly by service users as well as academics. Clare Allan, an ex-patient who has written about her experiences with mental health services, argues that there is nothing about “mental illness” of which to be proud. Although she recognizes the stigma faced by mental health patients, she understands Mad Pride as essentially a tactic to bolster the self-esteem of service users who, for years, have been subjected to stigma and disrespect in society and degrading treatment by services; she writes:
Mental illness is not an identity. Nor is it something I wish to celebrate . . . Mental illness is ruthless, indiscriminate and destructive. It is also an illness. It is certainly not a weakness, but nor is it a sign of a special “artistic” sensitivity. It affected Van Gogh, as it does bus drivers, plumbers, teachers, older people and children. Winston Churchill was reportedly manic-depressive, if so, it’s a diagnosis he shares with my friend Cathy, a mother of two from Peckham. Mental illness is an illness, just as cancer is an illness; and people die from both. (Allan, 2006)
A similar criticism can be found in the academic literature. Jost (2009, 2) writes that “mental illnesses” are not “different ways of processing information or emotion; they are disorders in the capacities for processing information or emotion.” It is absurd, she argues, to urge people to embrace such conditions and regard them positively. In making this point, Jost (2009, 2) draws a distinction between conditions that are disabling because the physical and social environment fails to accommodate variations in traits and characteristics, and “mental illnesses” that are “inherently negative” and “will always cause suffering” even if stigma and disadvantage were to be eliminated. Perring (2009) writes that for some of those who object to the movement, the analogy with Black Pride or Gay Pride—an analogy made in Mad Pride discourse—can only go so far as none of these are intrinsically disabling features of a person while mental illnesses” tend to be seen as such. That is why, he notes, it would be equally bizarre to have a Cancer Pride movement. Such views, no doubt, have wide currency among many clinicians who see every day in the clinic the effects of “mental illness”: social and functional deterioration, loss of friends and family, and the distress of extreme mental states.
There is, therefore, a challenge facing Mad Pride discourse and mad positive approaches: the problem of distress and disability. In this paper, I respond to the problem of disability by developing two bulwarks against the tendency to adopt, too readily, the (medical) view that madness is inherently disabling: (1) the normative basis of disability judgments; (2) the implications of political activism in terms of being a social subject. To delineate the scope of my argument, I begin with two disclaimers: first, my concern in this paper is disability and not distress. The former, on an initial reading, consists in limitations to/impairments of everyday functioning and participation. The latter—distress—concerns affective states such as fear, anxiety, or sadness. The two can be connected, of course; intense fear can impact on functioning, and disability can engender anxiety. This connection will be noted as required, but the two concepts raise different issues and require separate consideration.4 Second, my purpose is not to argue against the medical model of disability but against the tendency to assume it too readily in the case of madness. I begin by clarifying the criticism of Mad Pride and mad positive approaches.
II. Clarifying the Criticism
The problem of disability, as it emerges through the aforementioned criticisms of Mad Pride, can be more accurately stated as follows:
“Mental illness” is associated with disability.
This association is not contingent: disability is intrinsic to mental illness, which means that the various limitations experienced by individuals with those “conditions” are a result of the “conditions” and not an intolerant or unaccommodating society.
By contrast, so the argument would go, the limitations experienced by gay individuals were/are a result of a homophobic society that denied them equal rights and the right to be themselves. Once we correct for social discrimination and oppression, the limitations that gay individuals face will reduce. 
In brief, the criticism can be formulated as follows: even in a utopian world where there is absolutely no discrimination and a surplus of well-meaning regard that people show toward each other, “mental illness” will still reduce the well-being of those afflicted.5 To be clear from the outset, this statement cannot be intended as an empirical claim, not only because there are no studies of the fate of “mental illness” in utopia but because the proof demanded for this claim to work requires that the phenomena in question remain disabling for afflicted individuals once all socially discriminating and negative conditions have been removed. The problem here is that it will never be possible to assert that one has concluded the investigation, as it will not be possible to know if social conditions are the best they could be, assuming we can even agree on what “best” means. Given that it is not intended as an empirical claim, what exactly is the basis for it? To gain some further ground here, we can consider a possible response to this criticism, one that appears in the writings of some activists.
The response is to affirm that what is referred to as “mental illness” is a variation on human experiences and ways of being. The reason these variations may lead to problems in functioning has to do with a social world that is not set up to accommodate them and not due to a “disorder” or some intrinsic malfunction:
Most mental illnesses are seen as disorders because they prevent the person from functioning properly in the social world we have set up for ourselves . . . If the majority of the population was bipolar, things would be set up to accommodate them, and those without bipolar “symptoms” would struggle to fit in and understand the world. Is failure to hold up to the expectations of other people really a disorder? (Polvora, 2011, 4)
Both the criticism and the response to it purport to specify the locus of the problem: the former locates the cause of disability in the individual—in the “mental illness” to be precise—and the latter locates it in a society designed only to accommodate a particular norm. Essentially, then, the two positions here reflect a “medical” versus a “social” understanding of the limitations associated with madness. To arbitrate between them, I visit the social model of disability, a framework that has been substantially worked out in Disability Theory and can help make sense of this dispute.
III. Models of Disability
According to standard definitions, disability is comprised of a physical or mental impairment associated with long-term limitations on the ability to perform daily activities.6 For example, blindness, according to this frame- work, would be an impairment—or, for a less value-laden term, a variation in human functioning—that ordinarily would limit the person’s ability for personal and social functioning and participation. The priority given either to impairment or to social context in generating limitations gave rise to a number of disability models, the most prominent of which are the medical and the social models. The medical (individual) model emphasizes variations as the primary cause of limitation and prescribes medical correction and/or financial compensation. The social model, endorsed in some form by many disability activists and theoreticians, emphasizes that limitations arise from a physical and social environment designed and conducted in such a way that excludes or does not take into account individuals with variations in traits or characteristics (Oliver, 1990, 1996).7 The social model shifts attention to restrictive and exclusionary conditions in society and prescribes various sorts of accommodations to address this. In the case of sensory impairments/variations, for example blindness, accommodations can include practical adjustments such as tactile and audio signage.
It is important at this point to introduce some complexity into the notion of limitation in view of the kinds of actions involved. Nordenfelt (1997) distinguishes basic actions from generated actions. A basic action, such as moving a limb, is a simple and primary action that constitutes the first step in the chain that ends with complex, or generated, action (Nordenfelt, 1997, 611). The latter are actions describable at the level of the person in terms of overarching goals such as “writing a book” or “making a chair.” To clarify the notion of basic action, it will help to see it not in predefined terms but as something that becomes apparent by its absence. In this way, we can avoid having to ground the notion in an account of species-typical natural functioning and can leave it open to individual variation. Further, the notion of basic “action” needs to be broadened to incorporate other aspects of our fundamental abilities that are not ordinarily thought of as actions. For example, a certain level of concentration is required to be able to focus on a task. Concentration, according to the account advanced here, is not a basic “action” but a basic “ability” that underpins much of what we do.
Ordinarily, we become aware of the basic nature of some of our abilities when we are thwarted in realizing our complex goals. Ideally, the body is the medium through which we project and realize our intentions in the world. It remains in the background as a transparent medium until, for some reason, its interference with our complex goals renders salient a particular aspect or function. It can be a painful limb, impaired concentration, poor vision, or a heightened state of anxiety. All of these can be considered within the scope of basic abilities in the sense that they are disruptions to the taken for granted background of our complex activity in the world and become salient when they hold us back.8 The point at which this occurs is as personal as it is cultural, and we need not for this view refer to an account of natural function.
On this basis, we can distinguish two levels of limitation. The first level consists in the basic inabilities (typified in disability models as impairments or variations) that become salient when our complex activity in the world is disrupted. 9 The second level consists in the disruptions to the complex activity itself: the inability to work, socialize, or go to the market. Now, though an impairment constitutes a limitation at the basic level—a blind person cannot see, a broken limb cannot bear weight—it is not by itself sufficient for limitations at the level of complex activity. Complex actions are always performed in some physical and social environment, and the extent to which we can realize our goals depends, in part, on the match between the environment and our (in)abilities (see Amundson, 1992, 109–10).10 So, though a blind person may be unable to see (a limitation at the level of basic abilities), his inability to realize employment (a limitation at the level of complex action) can be addressed through specially designed working quarters that take into account his specific sensory abilities. Of course, one may wish to correct for the basic inability (the impairment)—to correct for loss of vision or hearing for example—but where that is not possible (technologically) or desired (e.g., Deaf Pride), then the variation/environment interaction can be scrutinized for impediments to the realization of specific complex goals.
Another helpful way to cash out the distinction between these two levels of limitation is in terms of the extent to which disadvantages are conditional on/produced by the social context. Amundson and Tresky (2007, 544) define the terms as follows:
Conditional Disadvantages of Impairment (CDIs): Disadvantages that are experienced by people with impairments, but which are produced by the social context in which those people live.
Unconditional Disadvantages of Impairment (UDIs): Disadvantages that are experienced by people with impairments, but which are produced irrespective of their social context.
Mapped onto the two levels of limitations specified earlier, basic inabilities would be unconditional whereas disruptions to complex activities would be conditional. Although I see a place for the distinction as such, I would not put it this strongly, as the notion of an absolutely unconditional disadvantage does not work. As I argued previously, a basic inability is made salient in the context of failing to achieve a complex action. The latter itself is relative to physical and social environmental contexts and hence is, in part, conditional upon them. So, it is more accurate to see this distinction as a matter of degree and not kind: as a distinction concerning the proximity of a particular description of disadvantage to one’s physical and mental states as opposed to the environment in which one is pursuing goals.11
The importance of the distinction between conditional and unconditional disadvantages is that it serves to limit the “oversocialisation” of the radical form of the social model of disability, which appears to deny a role for impairment in generating disadvantage (Terzi, 2004, 153). With this distinction in place, it becomes possible to argue, for example, that while a deaf person may be unable to hear and may not be able to listen to music, these particular “limitations” flow from the impairment/variation and are separate from the restrictions he or she may face in finding employment or watching the news when no alternative form of communication, such as sign language, is made available.12 The former are basic inabilities—whether or not they are undesirable—and the latter are the limitations caused by an unaccommodating social environment. As Amundson and Tresky (2007, 544) note, in disability rights discourse unconditional disadvantages “are taken as brute facts of human variation” and are not considered within the scope of disability claims and campaigning. Similarly, the social model—writes Oliver (2004, 22), the person credited with its introduction—“is not about the personal experience of impairment but the collective experience of disablement.”
Having made this distinction, it is important to note that there is no hard and fast way of drawing the line between unconditional and conditional disadvantages. The distinction is worked out in practice, leaning heavily on disabled peoples’ experiences and on what exactly the demand for social accommodation is about in the context of wider debates on these issues (see Amundson and Tresky, 2007, 553). Yet, the problem with the medical model of disability, and with the criticisms of Mad Pride described earlier, is that this distinction—if it is made at all—appears to lean too heavily on one side, with all or most limitations considered to arise from the impairment/variation. Such medical models conflate the two levels of limitation discerned earlier or recognize them as distinct but put too much emphasis on basic inabilities over disruption to complex activity. The area of contention then lies precisely at the boundary where what is put forward by disability rights activists as a conditional disadvantage is seen by advocates of the medical model as an unconditional disadvantage flowing from, or intrinsic to, the impairment itself. It is the latter, medical view that I consider problematic and to which I now turn.
IV. Naturalism, Normativism, and Disability
Critics of the medical model of disability have argued that the claim that limitations are “caused” by the impairment—that, say, not being able to access information is caused by a person’s sensory impairments—presupposes a naturalistic view of function (Amundson, 2000). Naturalism is the view that norms of physical and mental functioning can be objectively determined. Two well-known naturalist accounts have been put forth by Christopher Boorse and Jerome Wakefield. For Boorse (1997), a normal function of a part or process of an individual is a statistically typical contribution by it to the individual’s survival and reproduction. Statistically normal function is determined relative to the individual’s reference class, which is the appropriate segment of the species as defined by age and sex.13 For Wakefield (1992, 384), the natural function of a mechanism is the function for which it has been designed (selected) in evolution; it is “part of the evolutionary explanation of the existence and structure of the mechanism.” For example, the heart pumps blood, the legs move our body, and the visual system conveys perceptual information about the world: these are natural functions of the respective organs; they are what the organs were designed to do.
On the basis of their accounts of natural function, Boorse and Wakefield can then purport to specify physical or mental dysfunction in value-free terms as deviation from natural function. Both also recognize that that is not sufficient by itself to delineate the conditions that should be treated. For Boorse (2011, 28) and Wakefield (1992), a further evaluative component is required, which consists in the evaluation of this dysfunction as harmful in light of personal, social, and medical norms and values. On Wakefield’s formulation, disorder becomes a harmful dysfunction or—which amounts to the same thing for our purposes here—a harmful impairment. With this kind of reasoning, a blind person would have a dysfunction/impairment in the visual apparatus that, if associated with harm, would qualify the condition as a disorder. And given that according to naturalistic accounts function is a matter of objectively determined natural facts—with dysfunction being a deviation from normal function—then the limitation, the harm, that may arise from this is referred back to the dysfunction and not to a deficiency in the design of the physical and social environments relative to the functional abilities of different persons. This is because the person with a dysfunction, on this view, lies outside the range of normal functional abilities, and he or she lies outside this range not due to some inconsiderate value judgment but by the facts of human nature.
The problem with naturalistic theories, and therefore with the foregoing argument, is that attempts to define dysfunction in value-free terms have not been successful. This debate has been well rehearsed by several philosophers and I will only state their conclusions.14
Since its inception, Boorse’s theory has been subject to a lively interchange and many objections. Of particular relevance here are accusations of implicit normativism in both the notion of statistically normal function and the reference class against which this is to be assessed. With regard to the former, Bolton (2008, 113) points out that statistical (ab)normality does not by itself tell us at what point on a continuous distribution curve “deviance from the mean become(s) subnormal function.” Factors that in fact do underlie this judgment are those associated with the value component: harm and functional limitations as judged by personal and, more broadly, social values and norms. As a principle purporting to provide a factual basis for discerning normal from subnormal function, statistical normality does not work. With regard to reference classes, Kingma (2007, 2013) argues that Boorse’s account requires that he specify the reference classes appropriate to an assessment of health. Otherwise, any condition can be rendered healthy if we devise a reference class that shows it in a good light. For example, if we were to allow for a reference class of “uncommonly heavy drinkers,” then liver functions that would otherwise be considered abnormal would no longer be so, and those heavy drinkers, according to Boorse’s account, would be considered healthy (Kingma, 2007, 128). Boorse, therefore, needs to provide an account of the appropriate reference classes, and he needs to do so in a value-free, noncircular way, i.e., without introducing values into what is supposed to be a fact-based definition of normal function, and without presupposing the distinction he is trying to prove between health and disease (Kingma, 2007). As Kingma (2007, 2013) argues, Boorse’s account cannot provide this.
Wakefield’s harmful dysfunction analysis of disorder has also met with serious objections. Dysfunction, as noted earlier, is deviation from the natural function of a mechanism: the function that explains, in evolutionary terms, the mechanism’s existence and design. For our purposes here, the most relevant objection to Wakefield’s analysis of dysfunction is that which questions its presumed factual basis. For Wakefield, the norms underpinning natural function are natural (evolutionary) norms to be contrasted with social (cultivated) norms (Bolton, 2008, 124). The former underpin the objective status of dysfunction and the latter feature in the harm component. According to Bolton (2013), it is no longer possible to maintain a clear distinction between what is natural/innate and what is social/cultivated. It is now generally accepted that psychological functions are a product of an interaction between several factors: socialisation processes and genetic inheritance, complicated by individual differences and choice (Bolton, 2013, 442–3). These factors are not separable through the science we currently possess (Bolton, 2013, 442–3). Yet without a clear distinction, Wakefield’s account cannot tag exclusively onto a fact of our evolutionary nature in its bid to provide a value-free account of dysfunction.
If we accept the criticisms of these two leading naturalist theories, we can conclude that it has not proven possible to define function and dysfunction in value-free terms. We may accept this conclusion yet continue the search for a value-free, theoretical concept of function. An alternative position is to take seriously the value-ladenness of the relevant concepts and see where this may lead us. It will lead us to various forms of normativism about function. Here, descriptions of normal function are made in terms of what is good or bad, desirable or undesirable for an agent in the context of specific life situations and environments, in the present or a projected future. Those descriptions, though not pretending to have an objective standpoint in nature, are not any less “real” than naturalistic accounts: the core values that inform our lives, the projects we engage in, and the futures we plan are very serious matters. Indeed, it is a reflection of their seriousness that we tend to refer to those aspects of our abilities that may prevents us from pursuing them as “diseases” or “disorders.” But, the apparent objectivity of these terms should not obscure that they signal a normative and not a natural limit; they signal the limit of what a person and/or society considers normal, valuable, or good. These notions are set against a background of abilities that are considered the norm, in the sense of being the taken for granted foundations of a particular way of life in a particular social and physical environment. This has implications on how we can talk about disability.
It will help at this point to recall the problem that led us here. It was borne out of the need to arbitrate between the medical and social views on the origin of the limitations associated with variations in function. Advocates of the medical model consider most of the limitations to be unconditional, i.e., intrinsic to the dysfunction/impairment/variation itself. Given the prior analysis, we have a different way of understanding this claim. When we witness a person struggling to achieve some complex goal, we may refer this back to some dysfunction in his or her abilities. Now, we can see that the limit drawn by our reference to dysfunction is a normative and not a natural limit. Hence, when we say that a dysfunction (or an impairment or variation) is intrinsically disabling, we need also to give an account of the norms, values, and contexts by which we were driven to make this claim, and to come to terms with that being the basis of our judgment. The importance of remain- ing cognizant of this point is that in its absence we would not even occasion the need to perhaps examine those norms, values, and contexts and see if they can be modified in such a way that would reflect positively on that per- son’s ability to function and thrive in society through various sorts of adjustments. This would act as a bulwark against the gratuitous individualization of the difficulties others face, and the powerful tendency to medicalize their predicament instead of coming to terms with the social solutions that can be put in place, bearing in mind that that is what the activists are asking for.
Before proceeding, a final clarification: this argument for a normative reading of disability judgments does not entail that we must in each case employ the social model, evidently not; in many cases addressing limitations through medical correction or, more generally, intervention at the personal level will be recommended. What it does mean, however, is that the judgment as to whether we should intervene at the individual or social level cannot be made through recourse to some account of natural function and dysfunction, but by pragmatic as well as ethical factors including considerations of efficiency, safety, equality, and justice to name a few.
V. Applying the Social Model to Madness
Having established the normative nature of disability judgments and having developed the first bulwark against the tendency to view certain variations/ impairments in functioning as inherently disabling, it remains to be seen just how the social model can be applied to madness. In the ensuing discussion, note that the concern is with conditions that are long-lasting, have a substantial effect on daily activity, and where treatment is either not desired or not possible, i.e., we are concerned with “disabilities” and not acute or self- limiting problems.
Applying the social model to madness is not new; activists and academics have written about the potential and the problems of doing so. The disability movement has achieved some progress in making salient the contributions of the physical and social environments to generating limitations, with many accommodations to address this now enshrined in law. Developing a social model of madness in keeping with the social model of disability is seen as a way of counteracting the “medicalized individual approach” that is dominant in society and mental health institutions (Beresford, 2005; see also Mulvany, 2000). Resistance to this proposal has come from both sides. Some psychiatric survivors/service users refuse to be associated with disability discourse, as they do not consider themselves to have an impairment, nor do they want to be associated with the “pathologising” implications of the term “impairment” (see Beresford, 2000; Beresford et al., 2010). Conversely, others actively endorse the term disability as it creates a sense of community across the survivor/service user/mad and disability movements (Price, 2013). Yet, others are reluctant to use “disability” for the fear of being accused that they are not disabled enough; that they do not have the appropriate life-long impairments (Spandler and Anderson, 2015, 24). The reluctance of some within the Mad movement to accept the social model of disability and adopt its terminology has been interpreted by a physically disabled activist as reflecting the “disablism” prevalent within sections of this movement (Withers, 2014). That is, in refusing to be referred to as disabled and in asserting that unlike disabled people they have no tangible, “real” impairment, these activists are contributing to the idea that disability is a fixed thing and not an outcome of the interaction between individual capacities and specific social/physical contexts. Fear of increased stigma is another stumbling block for a shared discourse and activities between the disability and the Mad movements. Each group faces its own distinctive stigma in society, and to take on the term “madness” or the term “disability” is to take on an extra challenge (Withers, 2014).
Although these are important issues, the key point for the argument here is the underlying framework and not the terminology in place: what is of essence in the medical/social model framework is an account of the inter- action between the individual and society in relation to the production of limitations on everyday activity. With regard to naming, one may eschew the problematic term “impairment” for the less-loaded one “variation,” and one need not use the word “disability” at all. On the question of what constitutes a mental variation we don’t need to assume some account of natural function by which mental functions (and variations thereof) can be specified—the idea of natural function has already been problematised.15 Given the argument presented earlier, a relevant mental variation is one that is made salient when our complex activity in the world is disrupted. It would not be “schizophrenia” or “psychosis,” but the features that typically underlie these diagnoses such as voices, paranoid beliefs, anxious feelings, difficulties understanding social behavior, mood fluctuations, impaired attention and concentration, and others. These features can impose a range of limitations on the ability of individuals to realize their goals and to participate in everyday social situations and interactions. A few examples will illustrate:
A person who experiences chronic anxiety (or paranoia) finds it difficult to negotiate the long, crowded, bright lanes of the local mall and heads home without shopping. We can look at this disruption to activity from two vantage points: as a problem with the world or as a problem with one’s mental state (anxiety). Wherever we start, the other vantage point is implied: the difficulty of negotiating the mall makes salient my anxious feelings; my anxious feelings make salient the difficulty of negotiating the mall.
A person hears voices and converses with them, as she finds this helpful and affords her a measure of control. When she does this in public people give her strange looks and sometimes walk away from her. Due to this, on many days she feels unable to leave the house and her social isolation is increasing. Here, as with the previous example, the disruption to activity (social isolation) can be seen as a consequence of one’s behavior or due to negative social responses, with each view made salient by the other.
A person experiences fluctuations in mood; when “high” he can work for many hours on end, frequently overnight. Such episodes are followed by several days of rest during which he feels tired and low in mood. Due to this, he is unable to keep consistent employment as his line of work cannot accommodate the requirement for erratic working hours. In this case, disruption to activity (employment) can be seen as a consequence of his mood fluctuations or due to unaccommodating working arrangements. 
In each case, once a specific mental variation is identified, it becomes possible to reflect on the variation/environment mismatch and to formulate more precisely what exactly needs to change: modify the mental state/behavior, alter the environment, or some combination of the two.
The issues are different when the variation in question consists in a strongly held, nonconsensual belief: a “delusion.” For the sake of exposition consider two paradigmatic examples: the belief that one is persecuted by certain agents (persecutory delusion) and the belief that one’s spouse has been replaced by an impostor (Capgras delusion). On the basis of such beliefs, the person holding them may, respectively, barricade himself at home or avoid the spouse.16 For an outside observer who can see that both beliefs  are false, those individuals are subjecting themselves to unnecessary limitations; they are disabled by their beliefs. But for the believers themselves, this insight would not arise as long as they continue to hold the requisite belief with conviction.17 For them, the problems they experience are facts about the world—that one is unsafe and that one’s spouse is an impostor—and not the beliefs per se. In terms of the basic idea underlying the social model, as argued in Section IV, what is made salient by what appears to be disruption to daily activity is not one’s mental state, but facts about the social world. If I refuse to leave the house because someone is waiting outside for me with a gun, I am not disabled; I am sensible. If I am convinced that I am under threat despite there being no threat, then others may consider me disabled by my belief, but I would not. In this specific respect, “delusional” beliefs are outside the scope of the social model. They are brought back within it, however, in a different manner.
The “delusional” person may experience limitations of a different sort. He or she may experience discrimination, disqualification, and ridicule for the very fact of holding the belief(s) in question. In this respect, the discrimination in question would be no different to that which some religious minorities or sects face, except in relation to the question of numbers; the delusional person goes it alone, whereas sects tend to have a larger follow- ing. Here, we are brought back within the scope of the social model, as I am prevented from accessing the same rights and respect as other citizens due to the beliefs that I hold. A remedy could be to change the belief or, alternatively, to change the social environment by making it more accepting and tolerant.18
The earlier examples show that even though the issues are complex and will require conceptual work and ingenuity, it is possible to apply social model thinking to at least some mental variations and related behaviors. In fact, this approach to mental variations has made its way to a number of publications by academics, policy makers, and charities in the United Kingdom and elsewhere.19 These publications have issued recommendations on reasonable adjustments in the work place for people with “mental dis- abilities.” Underlying this is the understanding that by contrast to physical impairments, mental variations tend to be less visible, have a more significant impact on the social rather than the built environment, and hence will require adjustments that focus on social interactions and relationships (Department for Work and Pensions, 2009). Among the recommendations: time-out if one feels anxious or paranoid, flexible hours, reduced workload, quieter workspace, private rather than open-plan working arrangements, availability of contact with a support worker or friend if someone feels particularly paranoid, working conditions matched to a person’s tolerance for contact with large numbers of people, and combating stigma among col- leagues at work. The mental health charity Rethink Mental Illness (2012, 9) goes further, stating that stigma and negative attitudes of colleagues “can undermine adjustments that would otherwise be effective.”
Rethink is exactly right to point toward stigma as a major issue: without some significant change in how people think about madness/mental health problems, any proposed adjustments will be superficial and of limited effectiveness. Further, stigma and negative perceptions may impact on individuals’ self-esteem and psychological and emotional well-being, thus creating further barriers to participation.20 Yet in pushing to alter such attitudes, the Department for Work and Pensions (2009) and Rethink Mental Illness (2012) advance or support the line of thought that mental health problems are illnesses akin to physical illnesses, in the sense that they occur for reasons outside a person’s control (which arguably reduces blame), can be treated, are not to be feared, and are not a sign of weakness. However, as an anti-stigma strategy, this is problematic on two counts: first, studies have shown that the argument that “mental illness is an illness like any other” does not reduce stigma, in fact it is associated with perceptions of unpredictability, dangerousness, and fear (Read et al. 2006); second, this argument is antithetical to the demand for recognition of madness as an identity, where concerned groups do not see themselves as ill and where aspects of madness are reformulated in a positive light or, at least, neutrally. Rethink is correct in pointing out that negative attitudes can genuinely hamper a person’s ability to partake in the work environment; the difficult question is to specify what lies at the root of the problem in society at large.
To put this differently, impaired concentration, anxiety, paranoia, and social withdrawal are experiences that are commonplace enough not to generate any severe or unique discrimination from others. Most people are familiar with these experiences—think of sleep deprivation, jet lag, or a bad hangover—and readily find excuses for each other for them and, if they are generous, accommodate each other for them. What generates particular challenges in the case of madness is precisely the association of such experiences with phenomena that generate fear and distrust in others. To be anxious or paranoid due to the effects of alcohol overuse is not the same as having those experiences due to hearing voices or harboring fears that one is persecuted by government agencies or by invisible beings. The latter are phenomena that, for most people, defy simple, if any, meaningful explanation and from there engender a certain kind of disqualification and possibly distrust grounded in the apparent unintelligibility of these phenomena. At the point where this occurs, it is hard to sustain a social interaction in which the unique variations and traits of a person are noted and respected in order to create for him or her a more accommodating environment. More likely than not, when unintelligibility sets in we move from a position of accommodation to one of seeing the person before us as the main cause of their struggles. Intelligibility, therefore, is an important idea and merits a further look.
VI. Intelligibility and the Limits of Social Accommodation
There is no doubt that the variations discussed in Section V differ in significant respects when compared with mobility and sensory variations in relation to the question of social accommodation. One difference, noted by Pilgrim and Tomasini (2012, 634), is that at the heart of the social reaction to “mental health problems” is an “attributed loss or lack of reason.” By contrast, with mobility and sensory variations (physical disability more broadly), that capacity is not at stake. Assumed lack of reason, they continue, underpins the disadvantage and discrimination that characterize the social response to madness; it underpins fear and distrust as well as paternalistic limitations of autonomy. Unreason here is used quite broadly and ranges from not being able to meet social obligations (due to anxiety or depression) to failures in intelligibility exemplified by individuals whose behavior is underpinned by voices, bizarre delusions, thought disorder, or other states that for some may resist everyday understanding.21 Intelligibility emerges as a helpful concept in marking out more precisely an important, if not central, factor that deter- mines the limits of social accommodation of difference: the point at which we cease to consider discourses of social adjustment in favor of those that describe, in various ways, some sort of failure in the individual, for example, that he or she is “mentally ill.”
Consider the experience of hearing voices and its impact on behavior. A “voice-hearer” (Woods, 2013) may at times converse with the voices and be distracted by them. In some social contexts, as indicated earlier, behaving in this way can generate negative responses from others that may lead the voice-hearer into isolation and fears of appearing in public. In this example, developing social narratives in which voice hearing is normalized or marked out as a unique experience can engender a measure of intelligibility and tolerance of the associated behaviors, and this in turn may improve social inclusion for the voice-hearer. As Spandler and Anderson (2015, 19) note, this is what the Hearing Voices Movement has been seeking to do: to affect a shift from the view of voices as symptoms of illness to that of voices as meaningful phenomena. Intelligibility will depend on the kind of narrative put forward to create this meaningfulness. Some narratives draw connections between voice hearing, spirituality, and nonhuman agents such as spirits. Others see voices as denoting aspects of self and hence as offering a means for a more profound understanding of one’s past and identity.
For the voice-hearer’s interlocutor, intelligibility will depend on the extent to which he or she is able to accept the assumptions supporting the different narratives. And, herein lies the challenge of expanding our limits of the social accommodation of difference and our ability to conceive social adjustments: madness asks us to question our total worldview; to question our beliefs, values, sense of self, ideas of rationality, and personhood.22 The change required here is not to install a ramp or an alternate sign, it is to change notions fundamental to us as persons and to broaden the idea of what is possible. This is most evident in cross-cultural encounters. Consider, for example, a person who barricades himself at home on hearing the voice of a spirit threatening him with death if he leaves his house. Whether we consider this an “illness”—after all it appears to be a paradigmatic example of “action failure”—or a genuine threat, will depend on the extent to which we take the cause of the obstruction as real.23 In cultural contexts where spirits are considered to exist and to have a say in human affairs, that person’s self-imposed incarceration may appear to others as a sensible course of action until the spirit is dealt with. In cultural contexts where the “spirit” is understood as alienated mental content—objectified aspects of self—that person may be considered “ill. ”
While we are on the theme of cross-cultural encounters, we can consider other phenomena that appear to really defy intelligibility across cultural contexts. Such phenomena, thought disorder, for example, do not enjoy the “collective reasonableness” and positive reframing achieved by, say, the Hearing Voices Movement (Pilgrim and Tomasini, 2012, 642; Spandler and Anderson, 2015, 18–9). Jones and Kelly (2015, 47), mental health activists and academics, assert that “the struggles of a distressed individual who can nevertheless communicate with others, can and must be distinguished from an individual with thought disorder so severe that he or she can no longer be understood, even in the most basic of ways.” For Jones and Kelly, the limit of intelligibility is thought disorder, which is the limit it would appear of thought itself. For other less accommodating individuals, the limit lies much earlier, being evident for them in the slightest eccentricity in belief or behavior. The limit of intelligibility lies at different places for different people and, as indicated previously, marks out the point at which we begin to consider the limitations experienced by an individual to flow from the variation itself. At this point, we cease to consider changing social behavior in favor of changing the individual.
There are two bulwarks against this move or, at least, against assuming it too readily. The first has already been mentioned earlier and concerns the need to specify the values and standards by which one was driven to regard a particular variation as intrinsically disabling. In doing so, one may give more thought to the possibility of changing those standards in a way that would permit a broader accommodation of difference. The second bulwark arises from political activism: from the very demand for social justice raised by activists.
VII. Political Activism and the Social Subject
Mad Pride activists demand change in the social beliefs, norms, values, and overall practices that define madness/mental illness—essentially society’s total understanding and treatment of these “conditions.” The expectation is for society to change to accommodate a unique identity or culture. Hence, a major site of change is the reductive, discriminatory, and disrespectful language that dominates public and professional narratives, a language in which key terms all indicate deficit and pathology: disease, illness, disorder, delusion, hallucination, and, of course, “madness” itself before its reclamation by activists. In this respect, Mad Pride’s demands lie on a par with demands for recognition long voiced by the more familiar collective identities constructed around race, gender, and sexuality. Indeed, as indicated at the outset, the analogy with Gay and Black rights is central to the discourse and is frequently pointed out. In urging cultural change, the demands of Mad Pride go beyond the equalization of civil rights irrespective of difference (which requires a politics of equality that rejects discrimination on the basis of morally irrelevant features) but, rather, the recognition of that difference as a matter of social justice: the distinctness of the identity in question, its claim to respect and equality.
The demand that society should change to accommodate a broader range of variations as a matter of justice implies that the person making this demand is a social subject. What is meant by “social subject” will shortly become apparent, but as an approximation it can be taken to mean a human being who sees oneself and sees others as engaged in a shared project in which each individual’s well-being is at stake and equally matters. Now at first sight, this claim may appear paradoxical, for a popular view in both lay and scholarly accounts is that a central aspect of madness (or of “schizophrenia”) is the dis-sociality of the subject; a sign of mad subjects’ madness is their withdrawal from society. For example, a person with severe paranoia may have a radical, sometimes global, loss of interpersonal trust; for that per- son, others appear not as co-participants in a shared project but as a threat to one’s existence. In a related manner, the phenomenological psychopathology literature describes the “schizophrenic” person as having a crisis of intersubjectivity; a disruption to the two fundamental poles of social reality: sensus communis and attunement.24 Other times the “schizophrenic” person is described as having a disorder of consciousness and self-awareness; an ipseity disturbance characterized by hyperreflexivity and diminished self- affection (this view also concerns the “schizophrenic” person’s dis-sociality but starts from subjectivity rather than intersubjectivity).25 These accounts may seem to invalidate the idea that the “schizophrenic” person can be a social subject in the sense described earlier. If one accepts this conclusion, how do we make sense of those making the demand for social justice? One (cynical) approach is to claim that Mad Pride activists are not really mad at all. Another approach is to argue that the issue here is a matter of scope: the phenomena referred to by phenomenological psychopathology are at the far-end of the spectrum of sociality and are not representative of all “schizo- phrenic,” “psychotic” or mad experiences.26 I reject the first approach and accept a qualified version of the second, as will be evident in what follows. But first, I return to the idea of the social subject implied by the demands of activists.
Implied by the demand for the accommodation of a broader range of variations as a matter of justice are, at least, the following:
An understanding of oneself as an individual among others.
An understanding that individuals are different in some respects from each other, i.e., human diversity.
An understanding that individual well-being depends, in part, on the sustenance provided by social interactions and arrangements.
The ability to see oneself as part of a smaller group that is part of wider society.
An understanding of oneself as a person who possesses rights and whose claims merit recognition.
An understanding that others too possess rights (this is already implied by the way in which the demand is couched in the language of justice and fairness). 
In short, what is implied by the demand is a view on social justice and an understanding of society. Returning to the limits of intelligibility discussed in Section VI, we can say that by virtue of making this demand—notwithstanding the unintelligibility of specific experiences or behaviors—the person should be seen as a candidate for the social accommodation of difference rather than the medical (individual) correction (treatment) of behavior; the demand should act as a bulwark against the prioritization of an individual approach. The reason this is so is that the demand trumps the objection against social accommodation. In the terms raised here, this objection can be put as follows: mad individuals are, as it were, outside society, and to argue for accommodating their behaviors and mental variations is to risk losing society altogether, grounded as it is in shared rules and assumptions. The political demand demonstrates the person’s sociality and appreciation of the shared meta-project that is society, and hence refutes this objection.
Returning to the point I made earlier concerning the scope of sociality, it is true that some mad (or “schizophrenic”) experiences appear incompatible with sociality, a point made in phenomenological psychopathology. However, I see those whom phenomenological psychopathology describes as suffering with a crisis in intersubjectivity to be those subjects who are yet to see their situation in terms of identity, diversity, and social justice; who are yet to be brought to a conception of themselves as social subjects. Here, the principle of consciousness-raising that is described in the activist literature is instructive. This is the process by which people get together, share stories, see similarities in their situations, and interpret their predicaments as arising from discriminatory and difficult social conditions rather than individual pathology. Once this is achieved, a demand is made to change those conditions. Given this, an actual key goal within activist communities is to support individuals such that they are able to make that demand. In this endeavor, creating “collective reasonableness” in relation to particular phenomena is  also crucial. It may not be possible for some individuals to make the demand despite such support, and for others they may not wish to make it, opting instead for a more individual, illness-based discourse and intervention. But by redescribing the problem of sociality as a problem to be partly worked out in activism and political action, we are able to erect a bulwark against the tendency to see it in terms of disorder and individual pathology.
VIII. Conclusion
Along the decades, different groups have campaigned and struggled for respect and rights; some have been successful at achieving symbolic and cultural reparation, others less so. The enlarged scope of Gay rights in parts of North Europe, North America, and a few select other regions is usually cited as a success story. It is now pointed out that societies need to come to terms with the rights of transgender individuals and the respect they may be owed. Yet, Mad individuals, and madness more broadly, are yet to feature in the conversation on respect and identity, a conversation still dominated by framings that emphasize the medical idiom and the notions of distress and disability. This paper sought to address the problem of disability by erecting two bulwarks against the tendency to assume, too readily, a medical interpretation of the limitations experienced by individuals with the kind of variations in mental function that fall under the umbrella term “madness.”
The first bulwark arose from an analysis of the disability model that revealed the normative basis of disability judgments: when we say that a variation (or impairment) is intrinsically disabling we need to accompany this judgment with an account of the values, norms, abilities, and contexts that underpin it. This requirement, though it may appear too subtle to make a difference, actually brings about a profound change in perspective: instead of seeing the limit of our ability to understand and accommodate difference as an indication of a (natural) problem with the difference itself, we come to view it as a normative limit constituted by values, norms, and abilities that go so deep they appear natural. With this insight in place, it becomes possible to resist medicalizing difference, and reflect on what possible social solutions can be put in place to accommodate it.
The second bulwark arose from reflection on the implications of political activism. To demand, as a matter of social justice, that society changes to accommodate a broader range of variations in function is to be a social subject; it is to be a candidate for the accommodation of difference rather than the individual (medical) correction of behavior.
There is no question that effecting the recommended change in perspective is a challenging endeavor. Although applying social model thinking to mental variations (to madness) is possible—as I have demonstrated—it raises issues different from the kind of variations in physical function for which the social model of disability was initially developed. A key difference is the way in which madness presents a challenge of intelligibility; it asks us to question and broaden our values and beliefs with respect to fundamental notions such as our sense of self and overall worldview. Difficult though as that may be, at least we can now come to view this (apparently) insurmountable difference for what it is: as a radical challenge to norms and concepts constitutive of who we are. Whether we should attempt, as a matter of moral obligation, to change these norms and concepts in order to accommodate a broader range of experiences and behaviors is a further question to be considered.
Notes
This paper is based on a larger research project in Rashed (Forthcoming). Parts of this paper will appear in the book.
For accounts of Mad Pride written by activists consult Curtis et al. (2000), Costa (2015), Sen (2011), Triest (2012), deBie (2013), and Smiles (2011). See also Asylum Magazine (UK), Spring 2011, Mad Pride issue, Volume 18, No. 1. For records, flyers and announcements of past, recent and upcoming Mad Pride events consult the following websites: Hamilton: [http://madpridehamilton.ca/]; Toronto: [https://madprideto2015.wordpress.com/]; Liverpool: [http://www.liverpoolmentalhealth.org/mad-pride/]; International: [http://www.mindfreedom.org/campaign/madpride/events]. See also: Mad Pride issues of the Consumer/Survivor Resource Centre of Canada Bulletin (online: http://www.csinfo.ca/bulletin.php). Note that Mad Pride is capitalized to denote a group identity much like Gay Pride, for example. All links functional on July 19, 2018.
See DuBrul (2014), and the ICARUS project website, online: https://theicarusproject.net/mission-vision-principles/
Elsewhere, I have explored, with Rachel Bingham, some of the issues raised by the concept of distress in relation to the distinction between “social deviance” and “mental disorder” (Rashed and Bingham, 2014).
The term “well-being” is used here in a colloquial, non-technical sense.
See, for example, the UK Equality Act (2010), the US Americans with Disabilities Act (1990), and the United Nations Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities (2006).
See Silvers (2010) for a good philosophical overview of the social model of disability.
Note the difference between a person born with a sensory inability—blindness, for example— and a person who loses sight as an adult. The latter experiences a radical change in functional capacities that may be very distressing and disabling and may take some time to adapt to. On the other hand, a person born blind may not necessarily experience blindness as a salient obstacle in everyday life. This may change, however, if that person wishes, for example, to seek employment or further his or her independence. At that point, not being able to see in the context of a physical environment that does not take this particular sensory inability into account, may generate disability.
It is possible for a particular state to become salient without resulting in disruption to daily activity; a twisted ankle may cause pain and discomfort without rendering the sufferer immobile. Similarly, one may experience sadness, paranoia, or anxiety without this limiting social interaction or activity. However, the discussion in this section concerns disability, and the issue is disruption to activity.
A possible objection to this point is that a person with paraplegia and no recourse to a wheelchair may find it very difficult to move from point A to point B. Here, he is clearly thwarted in realizing his goal and the obstruction is not a consequence of unaccommodating social arrangements. However, disability theorists who endorse the social model for mobility impairments begin their argument by assuming the presence of a wheelchair. Disability consists in the limitations faced by the wheelchair user in environments with limited stair-free access. Critics could object that you cannot assume the wheelchair as it is not part of a human’s natural embodiment. Once you remove the wheelchair, they could argue, the extent of non-socially imposed disability becomes evident. A response to this objection is to think of the wheelchair as a tool that improves the functional abilities of persons who cannot walk. If I come across a 1-ton boulder and find myself unable to push it out of my path, I face a limit to my functional capacities, but I do not thus conclude that there is a disorder with my abilities (unless I am Hercules). To move the boulder, I make use of tools either to break it down to smaller parts or to somehow push it out of the way. Human beings use tools throughout the day to help them compensate for their functional capacities and accomplish tasks that otherwise would not be possible. The wheelchair is a tool in this sense, and it is acceptable to assume it as a given in arguments concerning the social basis of disability.
Note that the focus here is on the generation of disadvantage (limitation) and not on the factors implicated in the genesis of the variation/impairment in the first place, which can include various psychological, biological and social factors.
Unconditional disadvantages are referred to in the disability literature as “impairment effects.” These include the discomfort, pain, and inabilities, which disabled people face and are distinguished in the literature from the disadvantages experienced as a consequence of social restrictions and discrimination (Thomas, 2004).
Reference classes are included by Boorse to account for the wide variation of function within Homo sapiens: normal function in a newborn would not be the same as an 8-year-old child.
There are many critiques of naturalist accounts of (dys)function; the following are particularly helpful: Boorse (2011, 26–37) for a summary of the theories and the objections; Bolton (2008) presents a short critique of Boorse’s theory and a substantial analysis and critique of Wakefield’s; Kingma (2013) contains an overview of both theories and a general critique of naturalist accounts of disorder.
There have been some recent calls to adopt the discourse of “neurodiversity” as a positive replacement for the language of “impairment” (Graby, 2015; see also McWade et al., 2015). Advocates of this move believe that this would bring about a positive change: instead of “impairments” we would have a diversity of “minority neurotypes” that stand alongside so-called “normal neurotypes” as real and valid neurological types. These neurotypes, it is argued, should be accommodated as an element of diversity such as race or ethnicity. A major problem with the neurodiversity discourse is that it assumes that existing categories and identities (e.g., Autism, Attention Deficit Hyperactivity Disorder, Normal, and Mad) can be traced back to a shared “neurology.” But, our identifications and categorizations of behavior—as is now generally accepted in the domain of mental health—do not “cut nature at the joints” or reflect natural discontinuities. If so, then there is not much sense in the claim that there are distinct neurological types essentially different from each other. Further, neurodiversity raises a number of difficult questions; for example: what exactly is a “normal” neurotype? Do all “normals” share one neurotype? Do all people with “autism” share one neurotype? Neurodiversity may be important from an activism point of view, but as an argument it does not work.
Not all “deluded” individuals act on their beliefs, a phenomenon known as double bookkeeping (see Sass and Pienkos, 2013, 646–50). An oft used example is that of the man locked in an asylum who believes he is Napoleon yet does nothing toward exercising his regal powers.
This can change if the person develops primary insight into the delusional nature of the belief; if he or she is able to see that it is false, that he is not persecuted and that her husband is not an impostor. In such cases the person loses conviction in the belief and is able to see that it really was determining behavior in limiting ways.
Making society more tolerant is a solution that tends to be pursued in communities that advance notions of free speech and multicultural acceptance. The flip side of this tolerance is for the groups in question to develop secondary insight (a point which also applies to the “delusional” person). Secondary insight refers to subjects’ abilities to see their beliefs from the point of view of common social values and norms, and in doing so to see that others may find those beliefs unusual or bizarre. The benefit of secondary insight is that it introduces appreciation of what others’ views are without requiring agreement with those views. It allows contrasting beliefs to exist side by side, with both groups remaining aware that it will be difficult to reconcile those beliefs with each other. This is to be contrasted with primary insight, which as a notion in psychiatric practice refers to the person conceding the falsity of her (delusional) beliefs and demonstrating awareness that she is “ill.”
See Heron and Greenberg (2013), Thornicroft et al (2008), Goering (2009), the UK Department for Work and Pensions (2009), and the mental health charity Rethink (2012). Of note is that the UK Department of Health now recognizes as a disability a mental health condition that lasts more than 12 months and affects normal day-to-day activity. Among the listed conditions that may lead to disabil- ity are schizophrenia, depression, and bipolar disorder. By being classified a disability, a mental health condition falls under the protection of the Equality Act (2010) and the United Nations Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities (2006). According to these acts, the state is under an obligation to provide individuals with disabilities the chance to participate fully in all aspects of life through provision of reasonable adjustments that promote access to and engagement with the environment.
This is referred to in the disability literature as psycho-emotional disablism (see Reeves, 2015).
In each of these cases intelligibility means something different. With voices, the issue may be that such experiences are completely alien given my worldview. With bizarre delusions, I may be struck by how patently false these claims are or fail to understand why this person is holding them. With thought disorder, there may be a more basic inability to grasp any meaning at all in what a person is saying. The point here, however, is not to parse out the different forms of failure of understanding (see Rashed, 2015), or to suggest ways of enlarging intelligibility.
In contrast, mobility and sensory impairments ask us, primarily, to question our embodiment. I say primarily because many physical conditions also generate huge stigma— human immunodeficiency virus (HIV), for example, or leprosy—and hence also implicate the self of patient and other.
It would constitute action failure in so far as it is a negatively evaluated experience of incapacity, where incapacity is defined as a failure of intentional action (Jackson and Fulford, 1997, 54). The example provided fulfils the two requisite elements for action failure: (1) there is a failure of intentional action (the person is unable to make his will effective and not due to an external cause). (2) This incapacity is negatively evaluated. (See also Rashed, 2010, 189–90.)
This account is found in a number of works, particularly the work of Giovanni Stanghellini (2004).
This account is found in the work of Louis Sass, Joseph Parnas, and others (see Parnas and Handest, 2003; Sass, 2003; Sass and Parnas, 2007).
A third approach is to cast doubt on the methodology by which the conclusions of phenomenological psychopathology are reached (see Rashed, 2015).
References
Allan, C. 2006. Misplaced pride. The Guardian [On-line]. Available: http://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2006/sep/27/society.socialcare (accessed July 6, 2018).
Amundson, R. 1992. Disability, handicap, and the environment. Journal of Social Philosophy 23(1):105–19.
———. 2000. Against normal function. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Science 31(1):33–53.
Amundson, R. and Tresky, S. 2007. On a bioethical challenge to disability rights. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 32(6):541–61.
Beresford, P. 2000. What have madness and psychiatric system survivors got to do with disability and disability studies? Disability and Society 15(1):167–72.
———. 2005. Social approaches to madness and distress: User perspectives and user knowledge. In Social Perspectives in Mental Health: Developing Social Models to Understand and Work with Mental Distress, ed. J. Tew, 32–52, London, United Kingdom: Jessica Kingsley Publishers.
Beresford, P., M. Nettle, and R. Perring. 2010. Towards a social model of madness and dis- tress: Exploring what service users say. Joseph Rowntree Foundation [On-line]. Available: https://www.jrf.org.uk/sites/default/files/jrf/migrated/files/mental-health-service-models-full.pdf (accessed July 6, 2018).
deBie, A. 2013. And what is Mad Pride? Opening speech of the First Mad Pride Hamilton Event on July 27, 2013. This Insane Life 1:7–8.
Bolton, D. 2008. What is Mental Disorder? An Essay in Philosophy, Science and Values. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
———. 2013. What is mental illness. In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Psychiatry, eds. K. W. M. Fulford, M. Davies, R. Gipps, G. Graham, J. Sadler, G. Stanghellini, and T. Thornton, 434–50. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
Boorse, C. 1997. A rebuttal on health. In What is Disease?, eds. J. Humber and R. Almeder, 1–134. Totowa, NJ: Humana Press.
———. 2011. Concepts of health and disease. In Philosophy of Medicine, ed. F. Gifford, 13–64. Amsterdam, The Netherlands: Elsevier.
Costa, L. 2015. Mad Pride in our mad culture. Consumer/Survivor Information Resource Centre Bulletin [On-line]. Available: http://www.csinfo.ca/bulletin/Bulletin_535.pdf (accessed July 6, 2018).
Curtis, T., R. Dellar, E. Leslie, and B. Watson, eds. 2000. Mad Pride: A Celebration of Mad Culture. Truro, United Kingdom: Chipmunkapublishing.
Department for Work and Pensions. 2009. Realising Ambitions: Better Employment Support for People with a Mental Health Condition. London, United Kingdom: The Stationery Office Limited.
DuBrul, S. 2014. The Icarus Project: A counter narrative for psychic diversity. Journal of Medical Humanities 35(3):257–71.
Goering, S. 2009. “Mental illness” and justice as recognition. Philosophy and Public Policy Quarterly 29(1/2):14–8.
Graby, S. 2015. Neurodiversity: Bridging the gap between the Disabled People’s Movement and the Mental Health System Survivors’ Movement. In Madness, Distress and the Politics of Disablement, eds. H. Spandler, J. Anderson, and B. Sapey 231–44. Bristol, United Kingdom: Policy Press.
Heron, R., and N. Greenberg. 2013. Mental health and psychiatric disorders. In Fitness for Work: Medical Aspects, eds. K. Palmer, I. Brown, and J. Hobson, 132–54. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
Jackson, M. and K. Fulford. 1997. Spiritual experience and psychopathology. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 4(1):41–65.
Jones, N., and T. Kelly. 2015. Inconvenient complications: On the heterogeneities of madness and their relationship to disability. In Madness, Distress and the Politics of Disablement, eds. H. Spandler, J. Anderson, and B. Sapey, 43–56. Bristol, United Kingdom: Policy Press.
Jost, A. 2009. Mad Pride and the medical model. Hastings Centre Report 39(4):c3.
Kingma, E. 2007. What is it to be healthy? Analysis 67(294):128–33.
———. 2013. Naturalist accounts of mental disorder. In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Psychiatry, eds. K. W. M. Fulford, M. Davies, R. Gipps, G. Graham, J. Sadler, G.
Stanghellini, and T. Thornton, 363–84. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press. McWade, B., D. Milton, and P. Beresford. 2015. Mad Studies and neurodiversity: A dialogue. Disability and Society 30(2):305–09.
Mulvany, J. 2000. Disability, impairment or illness? The relevance of the social model of disability to the study of mental disorder. Sociology of Health and Illness 22(5):582–601.
Nordenfelt, L. 1997. The importance of a disability/handicap distinction. The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 22(6):607–22.
Oliver, M. 1990. The Politics of Disablement. Basingstoke, United Kingdom: Macmillan.
———. 1996. Understanding Disability. Basingstoke, United Kigndom: Macmillan.
———. 2004. The social model in action: If I had a hammer. In Implementing the Social Model of Disability: Theory and Research, eds. C. Barnes and G. Mercer, 18–31. Leeds, United Kingdom: Disability Press.
Parnas, J., and P. Handest. 2003. Phenomenology of anomalous self-experience in early schizophrenia. Comprehensive Psychiatry 44(2):121–34.
Perring, C. 2009. “Madness” and “brain disorders”: Stigma and language. In Configuring Madness: Representation, Context and Meaning, ed. K. White, 3–24. Oxford, United Kingdom: Inter-Disciplinary Press.
Pilgrim, D., and F. Tomasini. 2012. On being unreasonable in modern society: Are mental health problems special? Disability and Society 27(5):631–46.
Polvora, 2011. Diagnosis “human”. Icarus Project Zine [On-line]. Available: http://legacy.theicarusproject.net/content/essay-persuasive-diagnosis-human-polvora (accessed on July 6, 2018).
Price, M. 2013. Defining mental disability. In The Disability Studies Reader, ed. L. Davis, 298–307. New York: Taylor & Francis.
Rashed, M. A. 2010. Religious experience and psychiatry: Analysis of the conflict and proposal for a way forward. Philosophy, Psychiatry & Psychology 17(3):185–204.
———. 2015. A critical perspective on second-order empathy in understanding psychopathology: Phenomenology and ethics. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 36(2):97–116.
———. Forthcoming. Madness & the Demand for Recognition: A Philosophical Inquiry into Identity & Mental Health Activism. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
Rashed, M. A., and R. Bingham. 2014. Can psychiatry distinguish social deviance from mental disorder? Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology 21(3):243–55.
Read, J., N. Haslam, L. Sayce, and E. Davies. 2006. Prejudice and schizophrenia: A review of the ‘mental illness is an illness like any other’ approach. Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavia 114(5):303–18.
Reeves, D. 2015. Psycho-emotional disablism in the lives of people experiencing mental distress. In Madness, Distress and the Politics of Disablement, eds. H. Spandler, J. Anderson, and B. Sapey, 99–112. Bristol, United Kingdom: Policy Press.
Rethink Mental Illness. 2012. What’s Reasonable at Work? A Guide to Rights at Work for People with a Mental Illness [On-line]. Available: https://moodle.adaptland.it/pluginfile.php/20622/mod_data/content/54370/Whats%20reasonable%20at%20work.pdf (accessed July 6, 2018).
Sass, L. 2003. Self-disturbance in schizophrenia: Hyperreflexivity and diminished self-affection. In The Self in Neuroscience and Psychiatry, eds. T. Kircher and A. David 242–71. Cambridge, United Kigndom: Cambridge University Press.
Sass, L. and J. Parnas. 2007. Explaining schizophrenia: The relevance of phenomenology. In Reconceiving Schizophrenia, eds. M. Chung, K. W. M. Fulford, and G. Graham, 63–96. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
Sass, L., and E. Pienkos. 2013. Delusion: The phenomenological approach. In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Psychiatry, eds. K. W. M. Fulford, M. Davies, R. Gipps, G. Graham, J. Sadler, G. Stanghellini, and T. Thornton, 632–57. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press
Sen, D. 2011. What is Mad Culture? Asylum: The Magazine for Democratic Psychiatry 18(1):5.
Silvers, A. 2010. An essay on modeling: The social model of disability. In Philosophical Reflections on Disability, eds. D. Ralston and J. Ho, 19–36. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer
Smiles, S. 2011. Indicator species. Icarus Project Zine [On-line]. Available: http://nycicarus.org/images/waxandfeathers.pdf (accessed July 6, 2018).
Spandler, H. and J. Anderson. 2015. Unreasonable adjustments? Applying disability policy to madness and distress. In Madness, Distress and the Politics of Disablement, eds. H. Spandler, J. Anderson, and B. Sapey, 13–25. Bristol, United Kingdom: Policy Press.
Stanghellini, G. 2004. Disembodied Spirits and Deanimated Bodies: The Psychopathology of Common Sense. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
Terzi, L. 2004. The social model of disability: A philosophical critique. Journal of Applied Philosophy 21(2):141–57.
Thomas, C. 2004. Developing the social relational in the social model of disability: A theoretical agenda. In Implementing the Social Model of Disability: Theory and Research, eds. C. Barnes and G. Mercer, 32–47. Leeds, United Kingdom: Disability Press.
Thornicroft, G., E. Brohan, A. Kassam, and E. Lewis-Holmes. 2008. Reducing stigma and discrimination: Candidate interventions. International Journal of Mental Health Systems 2(3):1–7.
Triest, A. 2012. Mad? There’s a movement for that. Shameless Magazine 21:20–1.
United Kingdom Parliament. 2010. Equality Act 2010 [On-line] Available: https://www.legislation.gov.uk/ukpga/2010/15/pdfs/ukpga_20100015_en.pdf (accessed August 13, 2018).
United Nations. 2006. Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities [On-line]. Available: https://www.un.org/development/desa/disabilities/convention-on-the-rights-of-persons-with-disabilities.html (accessed August 13, 2018).
United States Congress. 1990. Americans with Disabilities Act of 1990 [On-line]. Available: https://www.ada.gov/archive/adastat91.htm (accessed August 13, 2018).
Wakefield, J. 1992. The concept of mental disorder: On the boundary between biological facts and social values. American Psychologist 47(3):373–88.
Withers, A. 2014. Disability, divisions, definitions, and disablism: When resisting psychiatry is oppressive. In Psychiatry Disrupted: Theorizing Resistance and Crafting the (R)evolution, eds. B. Burstow, B. LeFrancois, and S. Diamond 114–28. Montreal, Canada: Mc-Gill- Queen’s University Press.
Woods, A. 2013. The voice-hearer. Journal of Mental Health 22(3):263–70.
0 notes
leadgen · 7 years
Link
Local Plumber Central Coast is your local plumber Central Coast specialist. If you have an issue with a blocked drain Central Coast or hot water system Central Coast, then you need a 24 hour plumber Central Coast or an emergency plumber Central Coast to service you. You might also reach out to a gas plumber Central Coast to help you. It’s important that you have a plumber Central Coast, Central Coast plumber, plumbing Central Coast, plumbers Central Coast you can trust. Drain Camera Central Coast and Carbon Monoxide Testing Central Coast are other service we offer to our clients. Emergency Plumbing Central Coast is important to your home system. Do you have a Burst Pipe Central Coast? Make sure to visit our contact page.
We service many suburbs including: Plumber Buff Point, Plumber Bushells Ridge, Plumber Calga, Plumber Canton Beach, Plumber Cedar Brush Creek, Plumber Budgewoi Peninsula, Plumber Budgewoi, Plumber Bouddi, Plumber Booker Bay, Plumber Blue Haven, Plumber Blue Bay, Plumber Blackwall, Plumber Berkeley Vale, Plumber Bensville, Plumber Bateau Bay, Plumber Bar Point, Plumber Ettalong Beach, Plumber Erina Heights, Plumber Erina, Plumber Empire Bay, Plumber East Gosford, Plumber Durren Durren, Plumber Doyalson, Plumber Dooralang, Plumber Davistown, Plumber Wyong, Plumber Wyoming, Plumber Woy Woy Bay, Plumber West Gosford, Plumber Wamberal, Plumber Tumbi Umbi, Plumber Tuggerah, Plumber Toowoon Bay, Plumber The Entrance, Plumber Terrigal, Plumber Tascott, Plumber Tacoma, Plumber Springfield, Plumber Somersby, Plumber Shelly Beach, Plumber Saratoga, Plumber Point Frederick, Plumber Point Clare, Plumber Picketts Valley, Plumber Peats Ridge, Plumber Palmdale, Plumber Palm Grove, Plumber Ourimbah, Plumber North Gosford, Plumber North Avoca, Plumber Niagara Park, Plumber Narara, Plumber Mount Elliot, Plumber Matcham, Plumber Mardi, Plumber Long Jetty, Plumber Lisarow, Plumber Kincumber, Plumber Killarney Vale, Plumber Kiar, Plumber Kariong, Plumber Kanwal, Plumber Kangy Angy, Plumber Jilliby, Plumber Holgate, Plumber Hamlyn Terrace, Plumber Halloran, Plumber Halekulani, Plumber Green Point, Plumber Gosford, Plumber Gorokan, Plumber Glenworth Valley, Plumber Glenning Valley, Plumber Fountaindale, Plumber Forresters Beach
0 notes